Some reflections on Laruelle, Fichte and the Byzantines

I’ve recently started investigating Laruelle’s writings, having been acquainted with his key concepts and informed that he was also influenced by Fichte. The purification of the One from the traditional stereotypes that have inhibited it in the history of philosophy and culture is one of the key themes of Laruelle’s work, with which I heavily sympathize as a Byzantinist. It seems to me that not only there have been historically too many stereotypes attached to in interpreting the Byzantines – or the medieval Romans – as the thinkers of the ‘One’, but that this has also been erroneously characterized through centuries. For instance, Plotinos: the ‘One’ in Plotinos viewed as a hypostasis is only the ‘One’ from the purview of the Intellect, whereas truly in its ‘essence’ the name of the One should be altogether negated and rather seen as the Nothing that is simultaneously all things, which Plotinos himself makes clear in the last Ennead. One more fatal mistake in history was interpreting the Byzantine philosophers and theologians’ One as something transcendent. From Plotinos to Damascius, Maximos to Petritsi or Psellos – even Palamas – no Byzantine thinker ever thought that merely transcendence is consistent to the thinking of the One. When Laruelle is emphatic on radical immanence without transcendence, I find it far more accurate than the descriptions which have been granted authority in the past. That said, I would only like to raise a few examples and parallels to Laruelle’s thought as I see it. Also, full disclaimer in advance: I am not yet fully clear about Laruelle’s own thought and I’ve a lot more work to do. If I’m anywhere wrong, mistaken or misleading please feel free to point it out. If I’ve left out something crucial in my representation of Laruelle’s views, please correct me.

Continuing off of the previous points, Laruelle’s emphasis on the vision-in-One is also highly relevant and accentuates his proximity not only to Plotinos or Proklos, but even later Roman thinkers, like Maximus, Petritsi or Psellos who insist upon this from a Christian point of view. While I’ve yet to fully grapple with Laruelle’s critique of Neoplatonism in this vein, it seems to me that his point regarding the ‘‘philosophies of the One’’ (qua Neoplatonism or Lacan)’s supposing of ultimate convertibility to Being insofar Being is given final objectivity and only remaining the ‘thought-of-the-One’ and not One-in-One is a bit unfair. I am unclear regarding the supposed absolute boundary between the science of the One and the science of Being among Plato and the Neoplatonists. Is this really true, for instance, according to Plotinos’ concept of theoria? I also believe that Laruelle’s critique of Neoplatonism is too general and misses a key historial nuance. The seeming priority of the term ‘One’ in Neoplatonism – which virtually all Neoplatonists wish to abandon in the final analysis, given that they understand its dependence upon the Intellect – makes us also forget that historically there was a conflict within Neoplatonism itself between the philosophers of the ‘One’, which in a Laurellean reading are those at the level of thought-of-the-One and the philosophers of the ‘Ineffable’, which is seen as the Nothing ‘‘beyond’’ (not in a transcendent manner) the One itself and the thought of it through the Intellect. The history of Neoplatonism is properly speaking the conflict between Plotinos-Proklos and Iamblichus-Damascius, the consequences of which would eventually greatly influence the later developments within medieval Roman/Byzantine thought. Indeed, it wouldn’t be mistaken to say that later Neoplatonism and even Byzantine Christian thought that of Pseudo-Dionysius and Maximus abandon the priority of the ‘One’, leading them far more closer to Laruelle than Laruelle might think. The last great Byzantine polytheistic Neoplatonist Damascius is perhaps the greatest representative here, whose self-declared leap into the void beyond the One – whilst preserving it, although not with the same priority – and the consequences thereof are interesting to think about with relation to Laruelle’s immanence.

In this respect, medieval Roman theology goes beyond the ontological and the ontic. However, we shouldn’t neglect that Laruelle is equally hostile to immanences that present themselves as immanence but posit it in transcendent fashion – this is why he differentiates between absolute and radical immanence, taking the position of the latter and identifying Deleuze and Spinoza with the former. He is opposed to ekstatic immanence as well as unekstatic immanence (Michel Henry), including that which posit it as Nothing. Considering Plotinos’ negation of even the One, and Damascius’ move to the Ineffable or Pseudo-Dionysius’ towards Darkness beyond the One – it seems that the relationship between Neoplatonism and Laruelle is more complex than it might initially seem. On the other hand, it is also an open question whether can we think the later Byzantine τοῦ ἑνὸς ἐπέκεινα: οὐδέν (‘‘beyond the one: nothing’’) epekeina in a transcendent way. There is a dramatic transformation in how the epekeina is thought in Neoplatonism and Byzantine Christian thought that cannot be mapped onto the traditional planes of immanence and transcendence, particularly because Damascius himself even says that to posit transcendence of the Ineffable is to miss it. In general despite his best efforts at times Laruelle does subscribe to the thesis that the essence of Neoplatonism includes that the One is beyond Being in a transcendent fashion, albeit what remains unthought is what ‘‘beyond’’ here means, given that the One in Plotinus and every subsequent Byzantine thinker is both itself, qua One and Being. Indeed, while Plotinos and the Neoplatonists’ position has often been described as the procession of all that is from a transcendent source, what is skimmed over is that the meaning of transcendence here is not at all obvious. This is why when Plotinus says that the One is nothing and all things, the other branch of Neoplatonism – Iamblichus and Damascius – rebel against this; precisely because of this immanence Damascius complains that by positing it there resurfaces the problem of the One’s independence from the system. By positing the Ineffable and saying that the Ineffable remains ‘beyond’ it, it seems Damascius is reviving transcendence into Plotinos’ immanence, but in the same breath he also adds with regards to the Ineffable:

Hence, too, when we have grasped with the intellect everything that is in any way capable of being known or intuited up to the point of the One, we think (if we must attempt to express what cannot be expressed or to conceptualize that which eludes all thought) we still think it correct to posit that which does not coincide with anything and is not part of any system and indeed so transcendent that in truth it does not even exhibit the mark of transcendence. For the transcendent always transcends something and so is not entirely transcendent, because it is conditioned by a relationship with that which it transcends, and generally has a fixed place in the progression of a system. If, then, it is to subsist as truly transcendent, it must not even be postulated as transcendent. In fact, the name that most appropriately designates the transcendent does not name it correctly, since it [designates] something that is already co-coordinated within a system, so that one must at the same time deny it the name. But denial (apophasis) is itself a kind of discourse, and that about which the denial is made is the subject of the discourse, but the [Ineffable] is nothing at all, and therefore no denial can be made concerning it, since it is altogether outside the realm of language, and it is not knowable in any way at all, so that it is not even possible to deny the denial. Rather, the demonstration that reveals the [Ineffable] to us, about which we speak, consists in the complete overturning of discourse and thought.

Considering Damascius’ infinite failure and simultaneous success of infinite conceptualization of the ineffable which goes into infinity without termination whilst also simultaneously being terminated, it might seem that a strange transcendence has been posited. And yet, to complicate things even further, take a look at the relationship which resembles that of immanence between the Ineffable and the ego:

When first we try to see the sun we see it from afar. But as we get closer to it, we actually see it less: finally we don’t see it or anything else, since we have ourselves become the light. There is no more eye of enlightenment.

Do we not see here something reminiscent of Laruelle’s own efforts to preserve multiplicities beyond Being through elaborating the essence of individuality before Being? We find this not only in Damascus but also in Proklos’ definition of the gods before Being itself, and in subsequent Byzantine thinkers’ attempt to grapple with the soul of the human being (think Maximos’ mikrokosmos – although here, as in Proklos, perhaps there is the reduction to the double level of the unknowable and the thinkable which Laurelle wants to think without). To attempt to describe the position of the Byzantine Neoplatonists and Christians and their epekeina through Western thought-styled transcendence would be a fatal mistake. But given Damascius’ move that entails an active abandonment of the law of non-contradiction, a move Damascius explicitly states in his work and justifies with relation to Aristotle, and the fact that it does not descend into Being – is this not reminiscent of Laruelle’s own attempt to think the One without Ideas, or without reducing it, as Laruelle describes it, to the level of the unknowable on one side and then thinkable on the side of Being? Coincidentally, this argument that Laruelle uses is the same one used by Damascius to justify that the One in Plotinus is not genuinely the first principle or transcendent because it relies upon the transcending of something, as shown in the quotes above, and that it is superceded by the Ineffable which itself cannot even be posited as the ineffable nor transcendent. It is always that which cannot be finally determined by thought, but is itself, the thought, determined by it. Is it not similar to Laruelle’s ‘‘real-in-the-last-instance’’, which fundamentally shows itself as foreclosed to symbolization? More crucially, it never falls to the level of Being; how strange it is, to find what Laruelle calls ‘‘radical immanence’’ in Damaskios’ ‘‘transcendence’’!

That said, Laruelle’s accentuating on the One-in-One being given without givenness with the additional point that it forecloses any symbolization is not only present among the above mentioned Roman thinkers – Damascius especially – but also later Fichte, whose influence on Laruelle is well-known. Perhaps there is a parallel with Fichte’s 1804 Wissenschaftslehre, whose aim is absolute immanence which consists in the movement of concept experiencing what it means for the One/Light/Life to be foreclosed to any type of conceptual mediation and grasping from the side of the concept or factical-absolute I, which continually in its ascent tries to reach higher and higher, successively sublating previous disjunctive contradictions into itself and experiencing the withdrawing of the Light from what the concept thought to have been it in the contradiction, having believed it was finally able to reach it and find itself therein through sublation. The concept, in other words, is continually forced to experience what it means to repress the One and how this logic is destroyed when the thought-of-the-One, to use Laruelle’s term, is itself destroyed from within the purview of the concept when it is logically shown that the concept’s essence is to yield both itself and the thought-of-the-One. Fichte’s later ‘dialectics’ or more precisely exchange is precisely this; a triple negativity of the Einsicht (Insight) which culminates not merely in the self-annulling of negativity qua absolute negativity, but in the absolute manifestness of the One which reveals itself as having had always already withdrawn from the symbolization/conceptualization of itself that coincided with it being transformed as an ‘‘irreducible remainder’’ to the concept which it cannot symbolize. Ultimately, the Absolute is neither the symbolization of itself or the irreducible negativity that is a transcendent remainder which reveals itself over the concept that retroactively destroys the stability of sublation.

This is later Fichte’s insight which enables him to move close to what Laruelle sees without relying on formal thought. The One has its movement that is immanently shown, just as much the concept has its own constructive-reconstructive movement. It is this dual movement of both the Absolute-Real and the concept in the 1804 Wissenschaftslehre that continually enables us to see the Absolute as the Real, and Fichte even provocatively says that we want to surrender to it, as the essence of desire and drive – especially inhering to that of the concept – is to find itself in the Light. Just as much the concept desires to completely absorb the Light and leave no remainders of it behind which, by virtue of the nature of the concept itself, necessarily occurs; Fichte also shows that the essence of its desire is to want to be broken by the Light, which includes not only destroying its symbolic representatives but the concept’s own being and the irreducible remainder which shows itself as the thought-of-the-One beyond the symbolic of the concept. Even this Real-Light that negates and destroys the concept, which is the beginning of the aletheology of the Wissenschaftslehre and constitutes the concept’s thought-of-the-One, itself disappears. It does because it is ultimately the product of the Concept’s objectification of the Light.

The whole of reality according to its form is nothing more than the graveyard of the concept, which tries to find itself in the Light.

The finale of the aletheology of the 1804 Wissenschaftslehre is the absolute transformation that reveals the presupposition of the Absolute-qua-Real that breaks the concept’s presupposition from within, given that in the final analysis of the ultimate conceptual content of the factical-absolute I as absolute relation of subject-object it is within its very essence to yield, in freedom, to the abyssal One that emerges through an absolute hiatus which is ineradicable, but wholly rational. This also means the yielding or the letting go of its desire to find itself in the One, which marked it as conceptual – the concept, in German means to grasp – which finds fruitful parallels in Laruelle’s description of renouncing the desire-of-the-One. This is Fichte’s insight which splits him from the mystical tradition, as well as those like Schelling who similarly insist upon going beyond the Concept; the abyssal One is Logos, which constitutes a completely new and radical rethinking of reason than that found in the tradition. Therefore, when Laruelle emphasizes upon the given without givenness and separation without separation of the given through advance into the pre-ontological and pre-ontic domains, the most radical aspect of Fichte’s thought is in agreement. To use one of Laruelle’s key thoughts, the One is that which determines the Thought-World as given, or the object of givenness. This is why Fichte describes the One as the ‘Unknown’ in one of his public writings and sees this as the movement beyond idealism, which finds a parallel in Laruelle’s description of the One-in-One as the Unknown for philosophy. The finale of aletheology is to think from within the One-in-One, and not thought of the One which belongs to the concept. This is the essential result of the ‘‘doctrine of truth’’, which fulfills the promise it set out at the outset: the return to absolute oneness which had been presupposed all along. As Fichte says in his 1801/2 WLs, as well as in his correspondence to Schelling, it is neither being, or identity, or both, or even indifference of both; it is simply the Absolute, and to say anything further than that is superfluous. This is what he says in 1804:

The Concept finds its limits, conceives itself as limited, and its completed self-conceiving is the conceiving of this limit. The limit, which no one will transgress, even without any request or command from us, it recognizes exactly; and beyond it lies the one, pure living light; insight points therefore beyond itself to life, or experience… to that experience which alone contains something new: to a divine life.

…The origin of absolute knowing is to be sought in something which is not knowing at all…

That said, it still remains to be determined whether or not Fichte’s transition to phenomenology in the 1804 WL is tantamount to the convertibility Laruelle speaks of with regards to his representations of Neoplatonism and Lacan or if his immanence is an another type of absolute immanence similar to Deleuze. Considering Fichte’s methodology and the emphasis on that only there is absolute oneness, how are we to think of it? It is clear, however, that in Fichte the absolute unity of facticity (the ‘‘is’’) and the One is considered to be a scientific question which does not shy away from either of the two. A Laruellean analysis of the beginning of Phenomenology would be an extremely fruitful endeavor, since Fichte purports to begin it from within the thought-according-to-the-One, given that the aletheology culminates precisely in yielding any type of thinking through the I and only on focusing the absolute thinking according to the One from within the One. However, it is also the case that the phenomenology’s Soll that is inaugurated is a conversion back to facticity, which necessarily occurs according to Fichte’s immanent analysis from whose standpoint the thought-of-the-One is revived because we had to make the (illusory) move from an absolute oneness that is a self-enclosed Singulum which has nothing outside itself and cannot ever go into duality, as Fichte describes it, into a oneness of duality. Fichte insists that is a true, albeit illusory movement – true and illusory at the same time – because there is only the immanence of Life/Reality. One might be justified in seeing here parallels with Laurelle’s thought on the decision and how all philosophy is unaware of it when it decides to split the World into dualities and binaries. Could we interpret Fichte’s transition, from a Laurellean standpoint, as completely aware of that very move being made whilst also recognizing Fichte’s efforts to retaining the structure of non-relation with the One and the remaining task of thinking as that from within the One-in-One?

Setting aside the reason why this movement occurs, which would require an extremely lengthy analysis, the question is: does Fichte succeed in providing a link back to the ontological and the ontic domains without losing his previous insight, or does he commit the same mistake that Laruelle ascribes to Neoplatonism and Lacan? On the other hand, could not Fichte’s conclusion also be described as very traditional to negative henology where there is infinite and limitless postponement to the conceptualization of the One, with the novelty being that Fichte thinks that this is itself constitutively inherent to the One-in-One, implying the impossibility of Laruelle’s position? In this way, we would see Fichte’s project as a speculative inquiry into the conditions of thinking from within the One-in-One. Furthermore, Fichte does see the role of factical I as partaking in this type of infinite living/progress; no longer searching for a goal it can never reach lest it falls into self-contradiction (absolute I), now the I is always ekstatic with respect to itself because it lives in Life, which itself can never be fully objectified and always introduces new content through infinite conceptualization (this is why, not only in the Addresses to the German Nation but also in the WLs he characterizes Life as being beyond infinity). Furthermore, we must never forget that Fichte’s thought, considering its method, would be fundamentally opposed to and hostile to Laruelle. Fichte is a philosopher of speculative dialectics and speculative movement, just like Hegel would be after him; and the 1804 Wissenschaftslehre wants to produce the insight in the person without depending upon any presupposition, axiom or formal thinking through the person’s own resources and thinking. If there’s something that Fichte despised, it is formal thinking that introduces terms without having produced them in an a priori-a posteriori speculative thinking. Even if there might be some agreement with Laruelle, Fichte would oppose it by calling his thinking lifeless with respect to the methodology, and thereby falling short of its stated goal – One-in-One – because it paradoxically reduces it to facticity and merely the thought-of-the-One due to the nature of its method. This is, after all, Fichte’s ‘art’ of absolute immanence.

On the other hand, there are weapons to be used from Laruelle’s point of view also; the thinking of One-in-One must be extremely rigorous and absolved from giving it religious attributes. Perhaps Fichte thinks it in extreme purification from religious attributes in the Wissenschaftslehre, but does he not yield to them in his public writings especially with regard to his reading of the Gospel of John? Considering his indebtedness to Spinoza and Deleuze’s late recognition in seeing Fichte as the renaissance of Spinoza and the idea of life as absolute immanence, is not there in Fichte the specter of positing immanence in a transcendent fashion that Laruelle is against? But then again Fichte is tantamount throughout the entire Wissenschaftslehre, especially in the last lectures of the aletheology – the 15th comes to mind – in thinking the One in its absolute positivity fully in itself. No wonder that he says it is the most clearest but also the most hidden territory! And yet when Laruelle claims that:

‘‘The One is a sphere of an absolute “knowledge” that is neither a certitude, nor an adequation, nor a hypothesis, nor even a problematic, but a knowledge (of) itself without modality. This sphere is not an absolute science in the phenomenological sense (that is, still universal), but the sphere of an absolutely pre-ontological knowledge beyond a relative anteriority, etc., … which is already or still contaminated by ontology’’

Is there not a profound link between this and Fichte’s conception of absolute knowing? Furthermore, when Laruelle claims that ‘‘The One is an absolute essence. It is immediate givenness. It does not know the mediation (of itself) of a relation. And, what is in this way given immediately is always the essence itself, the essence as it is and not a content or a property of the object. Inversely, one absolute essence, the Absolute, has the structure of immediate givenness.’’ – one could almost find, word-by-word, paragraphs like this in later Fichte. Is it not contained within Fichte’s concept of the Absolute that it stands beyond the unity of the transcendental and the empirical, which the Wissenschaftslehre otherwise achieves, considering its status as absolute oneness that can never go into duality (the Dyad)? Fichte’s experience of the Insight, and his absolute enthusiasm over it as that which is given without any type of givenness inherent to it; can we not see in here the anticipation of the vision-in-One? The Decision to split the world into the immanent empirical factum and the transcendental constitution, the cornerstone of Laruelle’s critique of philosophy, is thematized in Fichte within the concepts of the act and drive in his later Wissenschaftslehre and it is here where we should look for a dialogue between the two thinkers.

Further thoughts on all these topics, including with reference to the medieval Romans as an attempt to go beyond the circular and auto-positing thought of the transcendental-empirical binary, remains a promising territory.

Fichte and the Diabolical

In one of his last diary entries, Fichte talks about Napoleon as the ”diabolical” and ”devil”, because he was someone who corrupted the Revolution and subjected it to his Ego as the measure of all what is and what ought to be. He also very interestingly says that, seen through the prism of the WL, he had the ”form” of the Einsicht but not the ”content” – I add the following, but this is equivalent to saying that this amounts to, from within the terms of the Wissenschaftslehre, the destruction of all factical content in the transition from the end of the aletheiology to Beyng proper and then subjecting it to one’s Ego as the Absolute.

Beyng is the ”absolute I” (1804 WL) insofar as it is that which is self-constructing in, of, and through itself (it is not I *as* I qua subjectivity, but simply that which is in virtue of itself; it has no duality in order to be able to know itself *as* itself, hence why Beyng is not absolute knowing but Nothing); Napoleon, on the other hand, destroys all factical content and then sees all factical content as arising from himself as absolute Ego, without ever confirming himself as a necessary presupposition. This is because while he does, as a living personality, construct himself, he forgets the presupposition of Beyng itself.

The form of the insight, which is Fichte’s method, is always generally the absolute negation/destruction of factical content in order to show in manifestness (evidence) the absolute independence of the insight from facticity but also the preservation of content thereof in recognizing that the free self-construction of the ego presupposes another type of self-construction, that of Beyng. If one only has the form, then one is the destroyer as such. That this belongs to the form of the Insight means of course it is not Beyng as such, but it is still inherent to it. Perhaps the point here is that evil can only be overcome through itself, in a way.

Generally Fichte had a very uninterested attitude towards the issue of evil, but this diary note just before his death actually implicates that evil inheres to the essence of Beyng/essence of truth.

Fichte’s critique of the French Revolution and Napoleon

The following article is connected to the previous one, which dealt with Fichte’s analysis of a dialectic inherent to Enlightenment. This one will be followed up by Fichte’s dialectical analysis of revolutionary temporality.

Fichte is highly critical of the principles of French Revolution, French people and what he sees as critical in both of them as contributing to the problem of modernity (or the ”third age”, as he calls it), is then radicalized in Napoleon. In other words, he is the outgrowth of the problems inherent in the former. Fichte simultaneously affirms him and condemns him; in a way, Fichte’s position is simultaneously reactionary and radical. According to Fichte’s view, for the French and consequently the French revolution the formation of individuals is based on the unity of the people, rather than the unity of the people being founded on the presupposition of the (free) personality. More precisely, Fichte thinks that the problem is that the French revolution considers personality as a product of society and that society is in turn what is presupposed. For Fichte, it is personality – and freedom – which are the presupposition of society. Fichte here not only appeals to the history of the French nation but also more critically the Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen, in particular articles I-VI. The article I is ”Men are born and remain free and equal in rights. Social distinctions may be founded only upon the general good.”, while the articles III and VI respectively express the dependence of the individual upon the general will and the Nation as the only foundations of its rights and laws. The article III states: ”The principle of any sovereignty resides essentially in the Nation. No body, no individual may exercise any authority which does not proceed directly from the nation.” and VI states, more damningly for Fichte: ”The law is the expression of the general will.”.

Fichte completely rejects this, which is why his position is reactionary in the sense that he rejects some of the most fundamental and foundational principles of modernity. But he rejects them for reasons that are precisely not conservative; he believes that the French Revolution effectively betrays freedom in its essential sense because by doing this they have essentially revealed that they don’t actually know the idea of personal value, purely creative things and the essential freedom of personality. In other words, because they constrain personality by having it that which is dependent upon a presupposition (society) instead of being the presupposition itself, the French Revolution betrays what it tries to actualize in the first place. For Fichte, this means that everyone can be used for every purpose if someone is lucky enough to win the ”general opinion”, whilst a nation which lacks the condition of the development of a free personality means that internally the individualities, each with their special opinions, that are borne within the general will are arbitrary and thereby in order to protect themselves they have to find their respective parties that would present a front against other parties that would want to impose themselves upon others in order to verify their own ”truth”, that would finally become the expression of the general will. If the general will is the presupposition upon which a personality is founded upon, even if the general will may itself be a force that, as the highest and most real truth, is liberated from religious or monarchical presuppositions the personality’s freedom is only arbitrary because it does not found it in itself. The result of this is that the law, the force of the general will, actually does more to divide and destroy personality (and the ”general will”!) other than actually found it in freedom. More concretely on that later. This means that the French, for Fichte, I quote: ”…was in the struggle for the kingdom of freedom and justice, and had spilled its noblest blood in this struggle, but the French were actually incapable of freedom”. I’ll explain more why Fichte thinks this with relation his philosophy, but here is where Napoleon comes in.

Napoleon, Fichte notes, is originally not genuinely French but Corsican. That he is like this means that biographically and historically he was not raised as a child amongst the French, as a result of which the fatal characteristic, that he notes in the French revolution, was not present: which is the ”sociable concern” for the opinions of others. The problem with this type of personality and with respect to how it manifests in the French revolution is that it is not auto-poietic insofar it depends upon others and precisely because it is not this, when a particular person becomes a dominant factor within society (as in Terror) as following the expression of the general good – due to the perceived view that the personality is in itself nothing but something dependent upon something else more essential, the ”general will” – those personalities can be sacrificed for the sake of the ”greater good”. Now, Napoleon does not have this ”French” trait as Fichte notes and this is why he does something that is simultaneously something that Fichte approves of but also rejects.

Napoleon had, as Fichte says, ”absolute will”; he was autopoietic in the sense that he did not share the sociable concern and having received his education in France after his childhood, Fichte notes that what was extremely prominent for his success is that he was able to understand the circumstances of the revolution and its inner driving forces. Fichte sees Napoleon as understanding that the French people were a highly active mass that was capable of being reined in and pushed into a certain direction because first and foremost, Napoleon’s view according to Fichte was that humanity is nothing but a instinctive mass of power and that only very rarely there do emerge great Spirits, who are separated by thousands of years that are , I quote, ”destined to give direction to this mass”. In other words, Napoleon has something in him that is simultaneously what Fichte approves of – which is that he saw himself as a free personality that is not burdened by the presupposition of the society, but rather that he, Napoleon, will become the presupposition of the society.

There is a problem with this, however, and this is where nonetheless the ”French” trait creeps in. Even though Napoleon liberates himself from the presupposition of society and thereby has the markings of a free personality, as a result of which he sees himself as, Fichte characterizes it, a ”world law”, he separates himself from the ”moral law”. Now, when Fichte says this it basically means that Napoleon abdicates from the insight to see into that the formation of free personality is something that ought to be automatically necessary in itself, and since it is universal – or the universal presupposition of the entire world – he effectively makes himself, i.e. the free personality, contingent because whilst (negatively) liberated from society, he is incapable of making his own positing of himself as his own presupposition necessary. But that can only be done if there is an insight into that freedom qua freedom is in itself the end which makes him possible as such, or in other words: to recognize that freedom qua freedom is universally and at all times necessary. This is Fichte’s view: we are not ends in themselves, but the means to achieving the end – which is always already realized, but to whom we’re also simultaneously striving towards as it consists of our activity to be simultaneously this but also, more cruically, on our way to: freedom. Instead, Napoleon does not see this: he uses freedom qua freedom as a means in order for himself, egoically reducing freedom to his freedom, but thereby actually makes freedom qua freedom something merely contingent and therefore also himself. Napoleon fails because he contradicts himself. Of course, for Fichte Freedom qua Freedom is the abyssal Beyng itself, the Absolute.

Now, let’s go more into the details.

I want to explain what Fichte precisely means by that ”the French were incapable of freedom”, since it seems unclear at first, especially given the Declaration. The essential conclusions of the Declaration is that neither in the private nor in the public sphere one should make oneself a means to others, not even one’s own moral perfection; to be for others in every respect at the same time an end in itself, especially one considers certain articles of the declaration. The fourth article is that freedom consists in being able to do everything that does not harm or infringe upon others, meaning that one’s natural right to freedom has limits that ensure that others members of the society enjoy the same right. Article 5 explicitly shows how the law forbids action that are harmful to the purpose of society as expressed, while the article 6 expresses the general will and promises that all citizens have the right to participate in its formation either personally or through its representatives. Article 11 (something touted by Habermas) promises free communication of thoughts and opinions as one of the most ”precious of human rights”, which seems cruical to freedom and to forming not only one’s own individuality and its expression, but also the socius. So aside from the theoretic point that Fichte makes, what does he actually mean?

For Fichte, the concept of freedom must be the unity of the theoretical and practical reason – but, ironically, this means the abolition of the right to ”individual self-determination”, key emphasis on ”right”. Why? To portray this, he explicitly posits that Kant’s conception of freedom and that of French revolution, especially in its legalistic dimensions, is essentially the same: which is that right is posited in the possibility of linking general coercion with everyone’s freedom (coercion that enables the possibility of mutual delimitation of persons and thereby their individual freedoms). This is further grounded in the pathological driving force, according to Fichte, that makes compulsion a necessary component in its structure; that it compels people into following it. On the other hand, free personality in Fichte’s understanding means the ability to create one’s own content autopoietically and auto-telically, especially as seen in the WL, and that the personality is its own presupposition. This means that the personality has insight into itself. Compulsion that is inherent to law’s structure and that it enforces both indirectly to maintain itself in peace, or directly to break those who transgress law is contrary to free personality’s self-construction, which freely constructs itself without any compelling (and which is both, for Fichte, a priori and a posteriori). If that is the case, Fichte says, law does not consist in as Kant and the French revolution say, in the interplay of free will and general laws. Law is simply an indirect way to ensure the morality or correctness of the insight in one’s self-determination, as in some kind of a provisional replacement. In other words, it is closely linked to education insofar as it must accompany, and be accompanied by education to maturity whilst a human being, first as a child and then growing forms themselves according to their own insights (Einsicht), and this includes introducing the right to self-determination and self-determination itself as part of the self-understanding of freedom itself. In other words, law and right are to abolish themselves when its phase has been grown out of, they’re not absolute.

For Fichte, the whole idea of the legal order (more in the French and less Kant) is as a coercive order of arbitrariness to one another; there is no presupposition upon which they stand upon, since only personality can be a self-forming presupposition. The legal order may indeed be posited as the presupposition but it cannot make itself a necessary presupposition; it cannot posit itself.

If this is the case, then the legal order itself rests upon a contingency. Since it is an order of arbitrariness, everyone cannot but be compelled(!) to follow their lawful arbitrariness contrary to arbitrariness of others’ willing, which is in turn conceived as the ultimate and highest content that is derived from the idea of freedom, or from this perspective’s logic, the idea of man as an end in itself. The legal order circularly completes itself. But for Fichte this only means that freedom is taken as a pure vanity, as something purely arbitrary and thereby self-annulling. Again, for Fichte, people in the sphere of law are not an end in themselves, but the means to elevation to freedom. For Fichte, it is not we who are free and have freedom, but it is freedom which has us. Right which necessarily compels in self-determination, together with its subordination to society, fundamentally misunderstands self-determination and ironically, in its absolutizing, loses freedom.

Right contradicts the internal right and freedom to follow one’s insight because it introduces compulsion as its essential element. Therefore, the individual is compelled to follow their own understanding in such a way that it is delimited insofar as their understanding is not the right one unless it is the affirmation of the general will, upon which the understanding depends. But this is to make following one’s understanding rest upon something external to itself, and ironically, it is also unable to ever understand the law. It is unable to understand the law nor what it promises, i.e. the expression of the general will because they become transcendental, external measures which in themselves become must become impenetrable so that the relationship of dependence upon personality to the general will is maintained, and furthermore it is itself rendered impossible because the general will or the law cannot understand themselves.

Back to Napoleon. So if the above is true, Fichte asks: how will the legal order ground itself? How it will be posited in order to have some ground to stand upon, given that it cannot posit itself? We see that if the above dynamic is correct, then the legal order will eventually not only culminate in a paradoxical self-overturning by means of which it will destroy its own citizens – as the Terror did – but also try to find (ineffective) ways of trying to ground itself (the Directorate) that would try to work by ameliorating the public opinion. But if Fichte’s ontological analysis of the personality is right, then only the personality can be ground of the legal order, and not the legal order (the general will, society) itself. And so it happened: that ground was Napoleon in Fichte’s analysis.

Part 5 (THE END):

But just like the arbitrary law-order, so was its ground according to the spruce-man. In form, Napoleon ”had” the Einsicht; he was a free personality that broke through the fetters of the content of the law, making himself the, I quote Fichte, the ”overlord” and the ”absolute will”. But the form and content of the absolute will are what? Yes, it is this absolute elevation that Napoleon had done, but it is also the yielding of oneself to the presupposition: freedom qua freedom. This is perhaps the paradox inherent to Fichte’s philosophy (and what makes him different from Goethe, Hegel and Nietzsche); he rejects Napoleon because he was not radical enough in breaking through to the genuinely revolutionary presupposition, but rather subverted it by appealing to the reactionary essence of the French Revolution: arbitrary individuality. The problem is not that Napoleon willed to power; the problem is that Napoleon then did not the radical move, yielding the will to power by letting freedom qua freedom emerge as the only true personality (and therefore that necessarily personality is the ground of society), by demonstrating it both actively as he did, but also theoretically through the intellect. In this sense, Napoleon was the educator because he not only reformed and spread the legal order through France but also throughout Europe, however he did not do it with respect to the end in itself, freedom, but as a means in order to elevate his Egoity as the Spirit the leads the amorphous blind mass, humanity. Napoleon in form did everything Fichte approves of, but the content is absolutely rejected because Fichte considers that Napoleon was superfluous and effectively failed because he blindly repeated the reactionary presupposition. Because of this Napoleon actually was not revolutionary, because he did not innovate upon the presupposition he acted – the revolution actually failed to revolutionize the presupposition upon which it was premised upon and what it desired. The one who could’ve done it the most as the free personality but in fact radicalized its most reactionary trait that was inherited from history, and thereby ruined himself. Fichte’s dialectics.

In this sense, the French and Napoleon show that law is only empirical and a posteriori, despite their pretenses otherwise. This is what Fichte wants to demonstrate; that there is a world-plan but which is also simultaneously shown retroactively through empirical movement. Instead, Napoleon and the French revolution become something only arbitrary, and Rousseau is also blamed here because his notion of the general will is also only something empirical for Fichte. Because of this no actual new world is introduced by the Revolution, despite its far reaching effects.

We should clarify that yes, Napoleon and the French Revolution do introduce a new epoch (a new world, in a sense) but this epoch is not that of freedom, as they promised, but that of liberation from external authority. That is what Fichte calls the third age. Because of this, personality becomes arbitrarily free and it may manifest in infinitely many ”new” forms as it is seemingly liberated from the constraits of traditional society – through bourgeois society, capitalism, individualism, etc. – that insisted upon the measure of transcendent authority. But in itself it never actually revolutionizes its own presupposition, which is freedom. Instead it cruically inherits from the past the form of this presupposition they only changed with respect to its content which meant, among other things, maintaining the subordination of personality to society (the new transcendent authority) and rendering it as merely a posteriori (product of transcendent authority, which is its presupposition), whereas it ought to be simultaneously a priori and a posteriori (its own presupposition). In doing so it concretely manifests its faults in different ways, being unable to realize the contents of freedom, Beyng itself, and knowledge. Because of this, while Fichte’s form of argumentation seems reactionary his accusation is that the French Revolution was not radical enough.

One could also say that Napoleon does succeed for Fichte, but he does so whilst introducing, for the first time, an Epoch which is completely ground-less as Fichte notes; and, he adds, that which is opposed to every past and future epochs which makes it unique. The age Napoleon introduces is unique precisely because it culminates as indifference and liberation from truth and reason; all measures and hitherto values are abandoned, but the third age merely rests in this negative void through the emergence and demise of arbitrary freedom of opinions and personalities. In other words, Napoleon expands the achievements of the French revolution but also more cruically its underlying structure: arbitrariness. Hence modernity is characterized by the arbitrary freedom of infinite multiplicity of perspectives and personalities which ultimately abandon the intelligible and only seek any measure in one own’s sensible existence and experience. It is the age of, as Fichte called it, the ”death of ideas”. The way to overcome it, in Fichte’s mind, is precisely by revolutionizing the presupposition of the third age through itself.

Napoleon’s parallel in Fichte’s work is Alexander the Great. Alexander, like Napoleon, sets out forth because he is enflamed by an Idea (like Napoleon was), is a free personality precisely because of this and sets out to expand the world-view that Right is the essence of the world, just like Napoleon did the same. The reason why Fichte considers that Alexander was more successful in bringing out a new, a more self-coherent Age than Napoleon is paradoxically because Alexander died before he could ruin it. Not because Fichte rejects Alexander’s expansionism and his will-to-power – no, he affirms it as part of the Insight – but rather because Alexander effectively carried out the yielding, an (involuntary) self-sacrifice to the emergence of a new world to the Greeks, by achieving their Idea, that would show itself by itself. For Fichte, that’s Freedom; Alexander, like Christ for Fichte are as personalities ever-more affirmed because they did this great step and are therefore necessary (because they let the New, which transcends the I, emerge) whereas Napoleon is not.

Reflections on Fichte’s dialectics of Enlightenment

One of Fichte’s defining descriptions of the Enlightenment and the Subject that is born therein is that it abandons all sources of knowledge other than Experience; that Experience is the only verifiable source that there is, and that therefore all previous systems of knowing that had been produced ought to be abandoned. This radical break that is present within Enlightenment, according to Fichte’s analysis, includes ultimately abandoning Reason and Truth as such; since the age of Enlightenment is the liberation from all external authority and from this perspective the imposition of Reason and Truth as ultimate values or measures of existence are considered as having been created artificially throughout different systems and beliefs in the past whose validity is no longer taken into account, the Third Age – or the Enlightenment – contains within its own dialectic the abandonment of reason and truth. The subject liberates itself from religion, superstition, external authority and states that alone the subject should be, and moreover should be happy. Moreover, all that is must be fundamentally comprehensible in order to be truly accepted as internal to the subject; in other words, according to Fichte, the enlightened subject takes that whatever is not comprehensible or clear in itself, itself it cannot be.

Because of this, in Fichte’s a priori schema of the Five Ages, the Third Age alone stands unique; it is the only Age which is self-consciously opposed to all previous and all subsequent Ages since it is the only Age which stands opposed to and abandons Reason. The first and the second ages either accept reason as instinctive or in the form of external authority, whereas the fourth and the fifth accept it in the form of knowledge (as in the case of the former) or as art (as in the case of the latter). The Third Age, however, stands opposed to reason and thinks it has seen into its nullity – there is nothing but experience, we’re nothing but brain matter and what is sensible, whereas the intelligible is not only false but also ridiculous -and because of this, it pretends to have a superiority and elevatedness beyond all past and future ages.

That such positions have been entertained not only in Fichte’s time, but also especially after him can be seen not only in the aftermath of 19th century history of philosophy, but history of the West in general.

Why does Fichte oppose it? Because Fichte believes that there is a performative contradiction at play within the third age as he sees it. Insofar the subject takes itself to be the only real thing that there is and that only the internal – in this case, experience – can be the only source of its freedom and truth, it cannot but presuppose the very transcendental laws it takes itself to have abandoned. The enlightened subject strips and abstracts from itself all of the previous qualities it deems as external, only remaining within the confines of itself and its own experience, but this very abstracting and reflecting into the distinction between what counts as external and what counts as internal is inherent to it as a pure I. That alone the subject (the I) ought be, and that I ought be happy – this self-containedness that is expressed by the third age is the expression of the I as the pure concept because it presupposes – without this being made clear to it – abstracting itself from experience and the sensible in order to express itself to itself as that which ought to be in light of what it has declared as internal.

The consequence of this are far-reaching according to Fichte. Ultimately, it means not only the reduction of the I to the domain of the a posteriori but also the reduction of all previously held ideals which in themselves are always beyond the sensible, like freedom, to what can be simply calculated and determined as nothing more but illusions that we have created. It’s the age of the death of Ideas; it takes its personal well-being as fundamental, although it is increasingly caught into a contradiction wherein that well-being, on the level of the state and beyond that, cannot be achieved; the state becomes an oppressive system and uses violence in order to impose itself on an increasingly alienated subject which, despite the fact that it states, according to Fichte that ”…all this devotion of Life to the realization of an Idea is a mere chimera to which we ourselves have given birth…” it cannot help but create those very ideas themselves, like in the form of state where it assumes relations to other individuals among other things. But those relations are not sensible properties of some thing, or something ”visible” like a chair or a TV is; while the enlightened individual claims to be a self-creating personality by virtue of its liberation from everything hitherto external, it claims that all of its creations that are not sensible and experiential, are illusions; all the while it acquiesces to all these very structures in order to maintain its personal well-being. Then it either conceals this very fact from itself, like the fact that it presupposes itself as a pure concept remains hidden to it, or it willfully engages in this obvious contradiction and thereby assumes the standpoint of Ridicule, according to Fichte, whereby it laughs off as ridiculous any claim to an Idea or a truth whilst maintaining the above structures. That this may manifest in many ways – among them class struggle – should be obvious, as Fichte is arguably describing the logic of the bourgeoisie (and what Badiou would call ”democratic materialism”).

This ends up resulting in Enlightenment entering a dialectic whereby, since it subjects everything that is that it ought to be comprehensible – its maxim is, to repeat, to accept nothing but that which it can understand – it stands opposed to a standpoint that it is its creation but it does not recognize it as such. Fichte calls this standpoint ”Mysticism”, although it shouldn’t be understood as religious mysticism. If the standpoint of the Enlightenment, according to Fichte, is that of the concept, then the opposed standpoint is that which does not accept conception as the ultimate. Whatever content there may be, for the Enlightenment, its fundamental form must be that of complete clearness and comprehension; that form is conception by means of which all content that may appear becomes comprehensible. But it also necessarily gives birth to a new type of mysticism. What are the characteristics of this mysticism? First, Fichte notes that this mysticism is very much the child of its age; in other words, it does not accept external authority as its own criterion. It is not the Christian or Islamic mysticism which grounds itself in old traditions and religious writings. Instead, like the Third Age, this mysticism is ”internal” and liberated from what it sees similarly as external authorities. The key difference is that it rejects grounding itself on experience like the standpoint of conception does, and abandons it in favor of what it deems as beyond the sensible, albeit in a non-methodical way. This counterpart to conception, of course, is Romanticism; it is the pure withdrawal from what is sensible to the intelligible, but this withdrawal itself is taken by the form of a leap and not speculative argumentation. However it too, like the standpoint of conception, falls apart due to the performative contradiction it finds itself in.

The main contemporary culprit, unsurprisingly (since this is Fichte we’re talking about), is Schelling’s Naturphilosophie. Why does Fichte pick apart Schelling? Because, according to Fichte, it too fails to achieve what it sets out to say it does; it says one thing, like conception, but what is enacted is something completely different. In elevating the intelligible and trying to go beyond it through the intelligible – in this case, its Absolute, the Indifference Point beyond both subjectivity and objectivity – beyond any speculatively consistent method of argumentation, it fails to actually internally construct it within itself. Because of this its method of development to its standpoint can only be something contingent upon a fancy, and even the richness of content it claims to want to preserve – by restoring Nature to a transcendental philosophy of the I – itself cannot be achieved, because the method toward doing so is premised upon formal assumptions that themselves have to be accepted in advance in order to function. Therefore, the Naturphilosophie – the child of its age – contradicts itself; indeed, unlike the standpoint of enlightened conception, it attempts to preserve individuality as something that is not merely reducible to what is sensible but it fails to actually construct it from within itself. It finds what is genuinely essential about the I, but this essentiality is rendered contingent and hypothetical.

This is then the contradiction between conception and this new-found mysticism. On the one hand, conception takes everything that is as comprehensible and clear to itself in advance, accepting nothing but the sensible as the only truth – although it even abandons the notion of ”truth” ultimately, without realizing that it has always already transgressed beyond its boundaries, namely that of taking the sensible as the true because it has already predetermined it as that which ought to be clear. Furthermore it is unaware that it is always already abstracted from the sensible by positing that the I alone ought to be and ought be happy – since it will accept nothing but the internal – because to create the very distinction between the external and the internal, and moreover found itself on experience presupposes the pure concept that is able to reflect on itself and on sensible experience. It demands clearness and yet loses it all the same by remaining oblivious to what it enacts by saying it wants clarity; it thinks it has gained experience, without becoming conscious of the fact that by saying that it wants pure experience the fact that it says this means that it is already separate from it. It gains the very opposite of what it wants, although unawares; the pure concept. On the other hand, mysticism says that it elevates itself beyond experience to what is genuinely essential and yet this ascent in itself is not clear to it; it does not actually construct it, but it elevates this standpoint beyond immanent construction, which necessitates clarity, whilst claiming that it is internal all the same. But this cannot be actually done because it is not clear to this standpoint what the internality here consists in. It sees the ”mistake” of conception and tries to escape the confines of sensible experience into the realm of ideas, spirit, art, culture – the intelligible – and even beyond, but while it says that it has done this what is actually performed is the loss of the very internal essence it strives towards because it abandons clarity in the final analysis, which consists in intelligibly and internally constructing this essence. It cannot admit this, however, because mysticism thinks that would be a reduction to conception, reason and a system. That it eliminates what it perceives to be remnants of all this is necessarily to do so in how it conceives to make the leap beyond even the intelligible. But in doing so it has gained the very opposite of what it proclaims to want, although unawares; the sensible because it constructs its principle all too non-intelligibly and contingently, as if it is acted out of a blind impulse which it does not clearly understand. Since it assumes that there can be no systematic, deductive and self-constructing path up to this point due to the nature of the result, it fails; the result betrays that the method by which it was supposed to be reached is all too factical, contaminating the result. No wonder then, according to Fichte, that it thereby only remains on the level of nature and the natural (”Naturphilosophie”).

Let it be noted that this is Fichte’s view of Schelling and his elevation of the Naturphilosophie not only as something that is individually part of Schelling’s philosophy, but as a general template that describes what Fichte perceives to be one of the two dominant currents of his age. Whether or not is Fichte’s understanding of Schelling actually faithful to Schelling’s real views remains up to you, the reader, to determine.

Ultimately, if we set aside the representatives that Fichte uses, another way in which we may express the essential dialectic of Enlightenment which is, for Fichte, that of between conception and ”mysticism” is in the opposition between actuality and utmost possibility. If the standpoint of conception is the death of ideas, then it willfully accepts the status quo and thinks that there are no more possibilities to be achieved beyond the present state. The human being is ultimately nothing but an atomic individuality that ultimately will be made fully clear and comprehensible through the machinations of the State, power (+biopower), technology and whatever else that stands beyond it while the latter are maintained under the premise that it does everything in its power to satisfy the personal desires of said individuality and its drive to happiness. Of course, we can see the consequences of this kind of thinking in our present world. On the other hand, there is mysticism which elevates itself beyond what-is into what remains possible beyond this status quo and takes itself to immanently arise within the individual, but which itself – if we follow Fichte’s thread of analysis – is itself hypothetical and illusory because it does not actually construct itself. This mysticism founds for the first time after the Antiquity and the Middle Ages an Idea from within a self-creating individuality that frees itself from the tradition, but the way it goes about it ends up in failure. Socially, it may oppose its communalism to the atomic individuality of conception, but this community it strives towards actually ends up being something external just like conception and may ultimately devolve into tyrannical authoritarianism. The standpoint of conception tries to be self-moving (i.e., give ”purpose” to the I) by focusing on the desires of the atomic individual, but it enacts this by creating complete alienation between individualities; mysticism tries to be self-moving by emphasizing the collective, but the collective ultimately ends up becoming a transcendent, external authority to the individual that the individual was supposed to have created. The dialectic of Enlightenment consists in either accepting actuality and striving to ”improve” it from within but never radicalize it beyond it, or attempting to take a leap beyond it into what is not yet realized but remains its greatest possibility, which would ultimately fall apart in itself.

In a way, did not the history of philosophy after Fichte end up as precisely this dialectic? On the one hand, we have Hegel’s acceptance of the status quo and later Schelling who was opposed to the rigidness of Reason as Conception in Hegel, for whom indeed everything was clear and comprehensible in itself, and which took everything that is not as such to be negative within itself, and thereby self-sublating into clarity. Later Schelling’s opposition to this, by elevating God, the Unprethinkable beyond Reason is very much contained within this dialectic; as were the general tenor of Enlightenment and Romanticism. The progress and the flourishing of the natural sciences, social sciences (like sociology and historiography) and positivism meant simultaneously destroying and ridiculing speculative thinking, whereas in existentialist thinkers – especially in Nietzsche – we have the ultimate abandonment of the intelligible, or what they took to be the intelligible, and the notion of truth and reason as they took it as from within that tradition whilst maintaining fidelity to the notion of autonomous self-construction that conception, albeit in different forms, inaugurated. From a Fichtean point of view, is it not the case that two diametrically opposed thinkers, like for instance Adorno and Heidegger, are actually kindred souls due to their mutual opposition to the supposed rigidification of Reason-Conception in ways that similarly end up theorising, albeit not through speculative reasoning, into what ”remains” beyond it just like in the aforementioned ”mysticism” – with Heidegger’s turn towards meditative thinking and Beyng after the Die Kehre (which he states in 1966 is-not lest we reduce it to the ontic level of entities) and Adorno’s towards non-identity beyond the ”Whole”? Or how about their respective positings of other possibilities that remain inherent and higher to the actuality they lived in; Heidegger’s die Andere Anfang and Adorno’s utopia? The elevation of (non-formal) possibility beyond actuality, even if that may be through irrationality, phenomenology, materialist utopianism or difference contra the assertion of actuality through conception as it is by remaining within the confines of the bourgeois society and individualism presuppose the same logic. Both claim that speculative thinking has failed through their encounter with Hegel and assume that it may only manifest in that form; even if, from a Fichtean point of view, Hegelian thinking is only the culmination of the standpoint of conception (aware of itself as conception, but still only conception) and also a preamble of what is to come. It is an open question whether or not the Fichtean critique applies to the aforementioned view-points that pretend to go beyond the Concept, as a Fichtean contribution to the debate would consist in how the move beyond the Concept is carried out; that said, it remains to be seen if this form of argument obscures the essential aims of respective thinkers and thereby distort their projects in order to fit a schema. However for Fichte they would be both the wrong ways to overcoming Enlightenment.

The analysis that Fichte brings up here is in its form completely parallel to the dialectic between the ”Light” and ”primordial Concept” in the 1804 Wissenschaftslehre as a result of which this historical analysis by Fichte pretends to be both a priori and a posteriori. How the two correspond, and how the dialectic transpires there – and what is the resolution that the Wissenschaftslehre, as the pure transcendental ontology brings about – will be explored in a different article.

Fichte’s Insight: Aletheological Power

A lot of ink was spilled over how much Fichte’s original discovery lay in an original investigation into the structure of reflexion as inquiry into the self-originating conditions of the transcendental structures of experience by means of the absolute I, which necessitated an even more radical unity of concept and intuition, the empirical and the noumenal I by means of the position of self-positing, inspired by the original question of possibility of empirical self-consciousness. How does late Fichte differ from this, which was inquired into in previous articles, lies in his abandonment of the hypothesis of Tathandlung of the absolute I or the factical act of the unity of being and thinking as the necessary precondition of experience of empirical self-consciousness of itself, and advance onto the genesis or life, which is seen as underneath the absolute I, as the self-position which absolutely denies the disjunction into being and thinking and was dubbed by Fichte as what was long-lost to the tradition: absolute oneness.

We won’t focus on Fichte’s later transcendental ontology, which may very well be ”henology” if we stick to the usual erroneous interpretation that the systems of ”henology” are focused on the supposed ”one” beyond being; all great representatives of this tradition ultimately abandon this standpoint not only rhetorically but substantially (like Damascius or later Byzantine Christians). While Fichte rhetorically talks about the “one,” a person who is well familiarized with the methodological intricacies of his thinking knows that his standpoint is not inhabited by a totalizing absolute knowing or a supposed super-mystical entity that lies beyond all existence. We assert here that Fichte is the thinker of the pure difference between being and beings, or, as Fichte called it in 1811, between Beyng out of Beyng as being of beings (beingness, Seiendheit) and beings. The ontological difference between the absolute and the factical (the ”is” itself) is one of Fichte’s greatest insights: between ”Beyng” and ”Beyng out of Beyng” in his later language. Fichte is not the thinker of a super-sensible Beyond; for him there is only the Universe, and it is in thinking of his transcendental ontology that he is able to not only pose the question of meaning openly, but what lies ”beyond” it as immanent to it.

It is in understanding this that the question of the project of immanence can be answered if one recognizes, together with Fichte and Deleuze, that the deduction of transcendence is always a function of immanence and the production thereof. This is what Deleuze himself requested when immanentizing Spinoza even further: the substance cannot be seen through a top-down approach as producing its own modes but precisely in the opposite way through the modes, as the virtuality that emerges in and through the movement of the mode, or categories in Fichte and German idealist discourse. This is what Fichte provides, which grants us a connection to the essential fulcrum of Deleuze’s project. We saw this problematic through the Byzantines as well, which we shall call ”epiphanical” or aletheological mediation, as opposed to the conceptual mediation that dominates Western philosophy. Our task is to see this concretized in the movement of history.

But Fichte’s true discovery for aletheological historiography lies somewhere else. Fichte is a great theorist of power, even if this is not the primary focus of scholarship in the way we’ll formulate. Later, Fichte abandons the earlier standpoint where power is ultimately related to the absolute I and the movement of the finite I’s striving (Streben) against the world, ultimately defined with relation to the check and transcendental imagination, which oscillates between the I and the non-I, resulting in the production of non-form as inherent to the I (possibility beyond actuality) and constituting the non-I as a meaningful object of the I’s causality and striving against. Fichte’s true discovery only appears in his later presentations, which he prized more than his earlier ones. We agree with Fichte here and continue the path Fichte has commenced.

The Fichtean revolution lies in a conception of a power that is self-producing within the individual’s knowing; it is the essence of knowing and inner certainty, which is absolutely spontaneous and demonstrated through the individual’s own reflecting experience on successive disjunctive and self-originating movements of ontological conditions of knowing. Important to note here is that this is not a version of [rationalist] content innatism or preformationism, where the order of determinations of consciousness and being would be posited under an axiomatic thesis, which would imply that this content is preformatively innate to cognition of rational beings without the demonstration thereof by inquiring into its self-generating conditions in terms of a reconstruction as to how they are retroactively self-constituting. Therein lies Kant’s fundamental opposition to rationalists and why he saw that a critical inquiry into the conditions of possible experience also necessarily entails investigating how the content of understanding and reason spontaneously produce themselves, cognized in and through reflection as being the presupposition thereof [i.e., reflection and all other cognitive activities]. This methodological point, inaugurated by Kant, is key to German Idealists and Fichte; the essential freedom of human beings lies precisely in the fact that reason is not something outside of experience but is necessarily spontaneously and productively self-positing from within experience but not reducible to it—not only with the historical instantiation of sense-making in human beings but ontologically as the first principle of the world. Major German idealists see this demonstrated by beginning with a first principle with the least intensional content and the movement thereof, which is seen as immanent to it and thereby, in an autopoietic narrative, explains itself. It is through this that transcendental ontology, for the first time in the history of power, reached the conception of aletheological power, which was most elaborate up to that point.

Therein lies Fichte’s understanding of philosophy as art and absolute art precisely because the Wissenschaftslehre, even if it is a reconstruction or image of the most primordial conditions, posits its content without recourse to a given representation or mediation. It is absolutely original, and therein lies the essence of aletheological subjectivity as always producing the original, the new, and the unheard-of through the emergence of that which, in Fichte’s understanding, breaks the is and the present order itself. We find this formulated in one of Fichte’s statements on the relationship between the ”divine person” and the ”divine idea”:

The original divine idea of any particular point of time remains for the most part unexpressed until the God-inspired man appears and declares it. What the Divine Man does, that is divine. In general, the original and pure Divine Idea that which he who is immediately inspired of God should do and actually does—is (with reference to the visible world) creative, producing the new, the unheard-of, the original. The impulse of mere natural existence leads us to abide in the old, and even when the Divine Idea is associated with it, it aims at the maintenance of whatever has hitherto seemed good, or at most to petty improvements upon it; but where the Divine Idea attains an existence pure from the admixture of natural impulse, there it builds new worlds upon the ruins of the old. All things new, great, and beautiful, which have appeared in the world since its beginning, and those which shall appear until its end, have appeared and shall appear through the Divine Idea, partially expressed in the chosen ones of our race.

If we set aside the ”mystifying” terminology, Fichte’s breakthrough to ”Life” or Beyng beyond the Concept is what immortalizes his project and marks his having gone far beyond both Schelling and Hegel, including late Hegel as well. But the problem of his project resides in the lack of a genuinely historical account of aletheological power, because his project was satisfied with staying within the borders of a transcendental-ontological deduction. It is in this way that his thinking of power is still far too general, far too broad, and cannot, as it presents itself, provide a concrete, material account of how it functions. Even if one considers that he is nonetheless very precise in his writings on right, not only is his account there rather unsatisfactory, but it also does not fully address the historical question of aletheological power, power which lies underneath “sense” or “meaning”. As we’ll find out, it is the shadow of this history that in fact genuinely grounds Fichte’s own project and contains in itself a movement he is not yet aware of, even if his project is immanent to it. To put it in contemporary terms, we must be more Fichte (in its essence) than Fichte himself was.

Nonetheless, we maintain that Fichte’s breakthrough lies in his transcendental ontology where he goes beyond transcendental subjectivity of the absolute I and reaches the standpoint of ‘Life’ as beyond the disjunctive unity of being and thinking and an overall completely different mode of power and living. This breakthrough is important in the history of aletheological power, and one must not mindlessly try to ”materialize” this, even if that is precisely the premier goal of aletheological historiography. In a short passage from an 1811 text, he is able to clearly formulate the standpoint of aletheological power:

At this insight, that the material world is merely absolute limitation of the productive power of the imagination, one question still remains in part unanswered, namely: What is that which limits in this limitation? The question might be put: 1. What is the ground why life limits itself at all? To this the answer is, Because it represents itself in an image, and an image is always limited and determined. Or, 2. Why is life limited in this particular manner? This question has already been answered, in part, as follows: Because the original and absolute power of imagination is limited; and hence originates extension, quality generally, and externality outside of the Ego, all of which constitute the mere empty form of external contemplation, which has no inner significance at all. But we have already shown that the real Inner Essence of the world, as a resistance to the power of free life, must be something quite different, must be, in fact, itself a power—a pure noumenon, which no external contemplation can reach. This power or force is indeed the world, and, as such, the world is posited and altogether determined. Whence does this determination or limitation arise as the only genuine, true, and original limitation? Evidently through original thinking itself, and in the following way: The world, even in its inner character, as a force, and as a resisting force, is to be object of the causality of the one common Ego; and the force or power of this world is to be overcome by the power of that one common life. In this subjugation a certain determined power of life, peculiarly and essentially belonging to it, will, no doubt, make itself visible to universal contemplation. Now, since by the law of our science we never start from a presumptive world in itself, but always from life alone, how would it be if that resistance, the real inner power or force of the world, were originally posited and thought only as pure resistance and as nothing else, hence as that wherein the power of life and in opposition to which the power of life made itself visible?

The matter now stands thus:

Life represents itself in its unity. Being life, it is a power—a determined, peculiar power; and, moreover—since we know it to be a principle—an infinite power within its determinedness.

Of course, Fichte’s Spinozism shows that power is the overcoming of resistance, the absolute self-fulfillment that lies in overcoming and becoming, something that indeed Nietzsche and Deleuze will have emphasized in their own respective ways. But the essence of the world is itself a power that is in opposition to life, and it is the very limitation that limits life. Alternately, life is the one that is limited by its self-limiting nature in determining itself as the image of itself. The essence of the I with relation to the world as a resisting force against the I is to be that in which the I, as the image of Life, posits itself as necessarily self-positing, as that which strives in the world in constituting itself and meaning thereof, which expands itself beyond the domain of the pure I and into the social I throughout history, etc. It is the I that finds itself in the world, is thrown, and strives to make the world the object of its essence, which is why Fichte insists that the world ought to be the object of the causality of the I. But while this still pertains to the power of the world, we can identify this power as conceptual power—that of the absolute I, or, as Fichte will call it in his later years, the concept—that power is to be subjugated by aletheological power or the power of life. We must recall here Fichte’s definition of power: power is that which overcomes resistance. If the power of the concept is the resistance against aletheological power, then the essence of aletheological power lies in its overcoming of the resistance of conceptual power and its rise beyond its present determinateness within the horizon of conceptual power, which lies in the essence or inner content of the world with relation to the I. When one looks into Fichte’s thinking of historical ages and their transitions, one recognizes that Fichte’s, albeit not yet clear to him, understanding of what we might term ”transvaluation of values” is precisely through this movement between ”conceptual” and ”aletheological” power.

The principle of visibility, as annulling this infinity [conceptual power] is therefore in fact only valid within a certain limit; in its emergence it goes through a hiatus, as the absolute miracle; It can only be said that there is a relation to reality in itself (insofar as such a relation can be ascribed to absolute life), but by no means can this relation be demonstrated [conceived].

The conceptual power is nothing but the pure resistance, which is always to be posited and overcome by aletheological power. Aletheological power is infinite and, as Fichte says, a peculiar power. What this means is that its historical premises are eternal; as long as there is a sense-making being, the possibility of its manifestation are present. However, we must reiterate that despite the fact that Fichte finally provides a distinctly clear formulation for aletheological power and the possibility of its historical emergence, what is missing in his account is the material account of how aletheological power manifests throughout history in the contingent contexts in which it does emerge. This new historiography must properly think of the manifestation of aletheological power in all of its intricate dimensions spread throughout all social dimensions as that which is the inherent premise of every, what we’ve called, historically conceptual or intelligible/sense-making structure. It is to fill the gap that Fichte left behind. So, where does aletheological history begin, i.e., the account of the origin of aletheological power in, for instance, European history? Right at the beginning: the Greco-Roman civilization.

Fichte’s dialectics of the Miracle

Here I’ll dwell only on some respective differences between Fichte’s and Hegel’s methods and some interesting comparisons, per example as that of between Hegel’s “absolute negativity” and Fichte’s “absolute miracle” and how this relates to the Fichtean understanding of a revolution.

As shown previously, both Fichte and Hegel share the joint task of immanent thinking; we see this, per example, in Hegel’s introduction to the Logic and Fichte’s insistence that transcendental thinking (the thinking of conditions of possibility) itself is not enough, because as it was shown in Kant this ultimately results into the root of being and thinking that is not capable of positing itself. Instead it is simply posited by finite reflection as a root of the two. For Fichte according to the immanence of this position the root contradicts itself; as the root from which being and thinking originate, it itself cannot simply be posited a synthesis as a consequence of the arising of the two terms (synthesis post factum). If this root is not constructed in consciousness as producing the two terms (being and thinking) prior to their arising, it cannot be claimed to be the root from which being and thinking originate. In Fichte’s language, this means that it is simply posited by a finite reflexion and thereby obtains the character of a ‘fact’ – a fact, moreover, that is not properly genetic or alive because it has not posited itself but was instead by posited a reflexion that remains external to it, as is demonstrated by Kant’s admission that this root is wholly unknown. This is why the Absolute should be an absolute prius and a result for Fichte, or immanently construct itself and this be demonstrated – this is where Kant went astray.

This is also where Fichte and Hegel join hands, but also simultaneously go astray. Both of them want to have a presuppositionless starting point, but the way they go around it is different. They agree that this entails practically the negation of being and our thinking as thinking of being, and the reversal of this negation as arrival unto pure thinking. This does not mean that this is a thinking of pure consciousness- on the contrary. Consciousness is a term alongside being that is to be eliminated. This is thinking thinking itself and being in relation with itself and to itself independent of objectivity (objective world) and thinking as thinking of objectivity (finite subjectivity). For Hegel this entails elimination of all determinacy as such; pure thinking/pure knowing consists in purely reflecting unto itself, as itself and through itself. This means that there is no matter of thinking other than thinking thinking itself and this is pure Being or pure immediacy. Being in this sense is not only the elimination of all determinacy and all that exists; it is also that which contains all of it in itself. As it is pure, however, we know that Hegel does not rest simply on this notion but demonstrate that it is self-contradictory in its vanishing into nothing and that it is this movement itself that is its truth.

Fichte, however, does not interpret the presuppositionless beginning in this way. Fichte conceives it the following way: for him, the elimination of objectivity-subjectivity entails that pure knowing itself first consists in pure unchangeable oneness in which there can arise no distinction of being and thinking or unity thereof – unchangeable oneness. There are no terms in it. But for Fichte, pure knowing is simultaneously absolute oneness in which there can be no distinction of being and thinking or unity thereof – as it is *literally* independent of the division we were originally in and that we had to abstract from – but it is also oneness that nonetheless is the site of disjunction into being and thinking.

How? On the one hand, pure thinking thinks itself in abstraction from the act of abstracting of being (objectivity) and consciousness (thinking of being), so it thinks itself purely. In its own self-genesis through abstraction from the act of abstracting from both consciousness and objectivity, pure knowing for Fichte genetically conceives itself literally as that which is utterly independent from any division into being and thinking. It conceives itself without dependence on any duality. Is it then the oneness of being and thinking? No strictly speaking – it is simply the very act of genesis itself, i.e. genesis as genesis independent of any disjunction or unity. That being said, in reflecting unto itself thinking always introduces a duality and so it sees itself for itself as oneness of duality or as that in which there must necessarily arise the disjunction of being and thinking in which oneness passes over into. This itself is the disjunction in which pure knowing stands for Fichte: pure knowing as absolute oneness independent of disjunction into being and thinking (pure arising, in and for itself), and pure knowing as oneness from which the disjunction into being and thinking arises and the first movement of the Wissenschaftslehre. Both terms are equally valid, but as we know for Fichte they also annul themselves.

Here it is important to clarify that with this distinction Fichte utilizes a theme that he worked on in the Jena years: transcendental seeing or insight. It is that which, according to Fichte, is more originary and upon which thinking as judgement-syllogism is based on. This is why while conceptual mediatedness and intuitive understanding are the domain of the latter kind of thinking which culminates in Reason as oneness of understanding, absolute Reason qua absolute oneness is the domain of absolute insight which whilst being in unity with the former, it is nonetheless not reducible to it. It is absolute oneness that encompasses Reason of the understanding, i.e. oneness of duality but is not reducible to it.

This is why I want to focus on this particularly: Fichte’s notion of genesis and Hegel’s sublation. To my mind, they’re utterly identical but with one important difference – while the Hegelian Concept retroactively posits itself through the self-annulling of content previously in contradiction with itself (thereby this dialectic annulling itself in speculative unity), the Fichtean Light (Absolute) adds a further step to this. As demonstrated in the previous article, the Fichtean Concept follows the path of Hegelian sublation insofar as it demonstrates the move from the implicit to the explicit. The disjunction between the supposedly absolute oneness and the Concept negates itself – the contradiction contradicts itself – and what is revealed is what had always been implicit to these two terms, but is only revealed as having posited itself through the self-annulling ideality of the terms since they presupposed it all along. In other words, the Concept undergoes its dissolution as the foundation it relied upon turns out not to have been consistent at all; it loses its ground, i.e. itself and in this self-annulling of the grounding it posits itself as the presupposition. This is the Concept which is circularly self-positing without premises as Fichte loved to say. But because the movement immanently follows the beginning for Fichte, this also includes the revelation of the Light-Absolute which posits itself independently of the self-annulling content of previous cases that are needed for Concept to construct itself by sublating them. As Fichte used to say in the 1804 Wissenschaftslehre, the essence of the Light is to be circularly self-positing without dependence on any disjunctive term. This is the territory of the Fichtean ‘insight’.

More precisely, if the Concept constructs itself with relation to the self-annulling content of previous cases it sublates, the Fichtean Light is only successively revealed to have always already posited itself without any ‘dependence’ on the self-annulling and self-sublating of previous cases. But this indeed is its independent movement of self-construction that the WL promises alongside the Concept! Of course, this also means that our perspective on the Light always already retroactively changes itself as successive revelations change our perspective of Light. Strictly speaking, this is an impossibility in Hegelian thought. Here, to emphasize this again, this is not the sublation of the Concept which is revealed to have always already been the self-positing presupposition of the content which, being dialectically opposed to itself sublated itself in speculative Concept. This is the only movement in Hegel, beyond which there is none in his edifice. The Fichtean movement adds to this one more element; with the revealing of itself from being implicit to explicit, the Fichtean Light also moves from implicitness to explicitness: as that which had independently posited itself without dependence on the Concept or its movement of self-sublation. But this is still thinking; Fichtean Light does not posit itself outside of thought. This is the territory of Fichte’s insight.

Of course, it’s not simple just like that. But we can already see the Fichtean correction of Hegel’s understanding of truth as the movement from implicit to explicitness. There is a double hiddenness – not only that of the Concept, but also of the Light which itself does not depend on this content, but reveals itself all the same through this movement as evental. I say evental because this is the ‘radical manifestness’ that Fichte insists upon because whilst utterly immanent to the Concept (and inseparable from our thinking) it nonetheless is always the singularly new because its content is irreducible to the self-sublating movement and content of the Concept. However we also saw that the Concept always objectifies the Light and kills it. Or, to put it precisely, whenever there is the revealing of the Light, there is always the threat of it being swallowed up in the self-sublating movement of the Concept as the oneness of understanding. This danger keeps repeating itself constantly until the very end; whenever there was pure Light as the unique which emerges independently from the Concept’s content, it turned out to be the Concept’s own content it immanently swallows up in the movement of positing the presupposition (this in itself does not mean that the Concept is in turn beyond death; in fact we saw in the previous article every movement results into the death and subsequently as a result of it rebirth of the Concept). The Concept’s objectification of the Absolute lasts until the very end; only in the end the Light is truly, absolutely the authentic Event because the Concept’s self-referential, self-negating movement negates itself, meaning it relinquishes itself and yields.

In this sense, is not Fichte’s method prescient as it demonstrates the necessity of a certain movement which was on display in much of modern history when it comes to revolutions and receptions thereof; one thinks one sees in a certain revolution the authentic, undialectical and unsublatable Event but which goes on to disappoint the expectant viewer or participant as it proceeds to fall into its dialectical opposite. Per example this is what Hegel identifies nicely with the French Revolution and its fall into its opposite (Terror). Of course, the Hegelian answer to this dilemma is the rational state and rational system of goods – the Fichtean is to insist upon the French Revolution as the singular Event which, through its fall to its opposite reveals that it has always already objectified and killed the genuine Event/Revolution and whose sublation in the rational state (Concept) can only then precipitate the revelation of the genuine Event/Revolution and reveals that the objectification had already taken place. In the previous article, we saw that it is the subversion of freedom itself; the reduction of freedom qua freedom to the presupposition of the society.

The Fichtean answer is clear: revolutions always necessarily kill themselves not because they fall into its dialectical opposite and so they are revealed to have never been revolutions but rather, for instance reactionary uprisings; they were never revolutions to begin with because its dialectical inversion reveals that it has always already objectified and killed the ‘true’ Revolution itself prior to the inversion – the inversion, in other words, is revealed to presuppose this objectification alongside the negativity that inheres to itself as determinate content. This is the ultimate irony of the Fichtean position; the Revolution itself in its immediacy and what may seem the pure vitality thereof is the objectification of the Event, not its actualization (this is why characterizations of Fichte’s Absolute as radical immediacy are also wrong), and the factical Revolution in its existence depends upon this objectification or the killing of the Event, a necessary failure. This is why the inversion reveals not only the immanence of terror and failure to the revolution, or negativity inherent to its ”conceptual” content, but an even more radical failure of a completely different kind that lies beneath this.

At this stage, we also saw in the Fichtean dialectic that the Absolute negates the Concept; it is before the inversion of revolution that there is a different type of disjunction, which is the negation of the Concept by Absolute where the Absolute shows itself as the Lacanian ‘Real’ of the Concept (the Absolute cannot be symbolized, mediated, it is what breaks and kills the Concept in its self-mediating as an irreducible ”product” that emerges within Concept’s circularity-remainder in the movement of Concept’s positing of presupposition… – recall that Fichte says that the whole of reality is the graveyard of the Concept which strives to be in the Light). In other words, the objectification of the Concept and its devouring of the Light coincides with the Light’s negation of the Concept. It is only in and through the destruction of the revolution not only through its self-annulling (sublation of the dialectical inversion) that the revolution actually takes place, since it is in this self-annihilation of the annihilation that the objectification of the Absolute, coinciding with the negation of the Concept by the Absolute-Real, also ceases. This is Fichte’s triple negativity, if we understand the Absolute proper is the Nothing (not only ”no-thing”, but something which entirely precedes ”what-is”). It is necessary to pass through this movement – it is only through failure that the Light actually reveals itself because the objectification of the Concept, i.e. the Concept yields itself. To put it a bit daringly, the final movement is revelation of what had always been (but to which we could arrive only through the necessity of failure): the inversion of the Real into pure Life. This is another paradox of the Fichtean movement; as long as there was objectification, the Absolute could’ve been nothing but the abyssal Real; in the self-yielding of the Concept, the Absolute in turn yields to us which reveals not that the Absolute has forfeited its abyssalness – it hasn’t – but that it is pure Life itself out of which the Concept arises from and from which it is inseparable, as the I.

This is then what separates Fichte’s notion of the I as ‘absolute miracle’ from Hegel’s ‘absolute negativity’ – it is not enough to simply insist on the dialectical inversion and its speculative sublation per the Hegelian methodology. This only affirms the objectification without seeing its actual presupposition. Nor does this mean that Fichte renders the Absolute immobile and simply ‘waiting’ for the failure to realize itself; Fichte reserves for the Absolute/Light ‘beyond’ the Concept a different kind of movement immanent to thought (insight). The consequence of the Fichtean movement is not simply reconciliation and the obtaining of the absolute effect of the revolution in the form of a rational system of goods (the ethical state). This is the Hegelian solution, which is the resolution of the abstract indeterminacy of the Revolution into a concrete universality of the rational, ethical state which signals the end of revolutionary praxis. The Fichtean step is to turn the perspective around; the French Revolution had never been a ”revolution” to begin with, and therefore the ‘sublation’ of the revolution is the revelation of the genuine revolution, i.e. revelation of Being itself. The Concept’s self-yielding (the cessation of objectification through its self-annulment) to the Light in order to truly show itself is in turn the Light’s/Absolute’s yielding of itself to us because this yielding to the yielding is in fact Absolute’s yielding to itself (self-referentiality of pure thinking) – this is the culmination of the Fichtean dialectic’s positing of the presupposition. Fichte’s originality resides not in his notion of the abyssal Absolute that lies beneath and is irreducible to the disjunction into subject and object (that is the line in much of German Idealism, from Holderlin to Schelling): his originality lies in seeing the abyssal Absolute as the pure I (which is what Žižek, among other things we enumerated in the previous article, missed) and Reason itself. The result of this movement is that for Fichte the essence of the ‘self’ then resides in this activity of infinitely bringing forth this revolution onto the world. What this means concretely with relation to the philosophy of state (right), ethics, nature, etc. will be explored in other articles. The logic of this reversal however is clear enough: for Fichte it is only in the aftermath of the revolution that the revolution can actually begin beyond the infinite reconciliation in the concrete rational state.

…(This philosophy) raises itself to the ‘more than all infinity’ that is unchangeable, and in this alone it finds true Being. It perceives time and eternity and infinity in their rise from the appearing and becoming visible of that One which is in itself invisible and which is only comprehended, rightly comprehended, in this invisibility. Even infinity is, according to this philosophy, nothing in itself and there is in it no true Being whatsoever.

Schelling’s Critique of Hegel

Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph von Schelling (1775-1854) is one of the greatest philosophers of German Idealism. His Naturphilosophie was one of the most original contributions in the history of philosophy and was a conclusive break from the Kantian/Fichtean tradition of transcendental idealism. He wrote two philosophical masterpieces – On the Essence of Human Freedom (1809) and The Ages of the World – which would prove to be influential even to this day. We will not recapitulate the phases of Schelling’s intellectual development – we shall choose here to focus on Schelling’s critique of Hegel in his History of Modern Philosophy and draw the comparisons between Hegel’s Logic and Schelling’s The Ages of the World, as well as use some references from the Stuttgart and Berlin lectures. It is somewhat justified to state that Schelling’s conception of positive philosophy would have lacked a huge part of its foundation if Hegel had never broken off from Schelling’s influence. Hegel did, ultimately, go his own way – and he will become the culmination of what Schelling thought was latent within all philosophies of Reason – the dismissal of Nature.

“There is no greatness without a continual solicitation to madness which, while it must be overcome, must never be completely lacking. One might profit by classifying men in this respect. The one kind are those in whom there is no madness at all … and are so-called men of intellect whose works and deeds are nothing but cold works and deeds of the intellect…. But where there is no madness, there is, to be sure, also no real, active, living intellect. For wherein is intellect to prove itself but in the conquest, mastery, and ordering of madness?”

Introduction

Schelling criticizes Hegel for having destroyed the freedom of Reason by elevating it into a system of logic which, whose structure is designed, as a transcendental ontology, to (wrongfully) derive the world of actual existence from the world of logical concepts. What Schelling is effectively denying is that there is a logical system that can truly exhaust the entirety of God’s identity. Schelling’s viewpoint is that identity is always a condition of God’s revelation through creation. What this means for Schelling is that identity, conceived in this way, is always an ongoing process – it is that which supports and underlies the true beginning (in contrast to the eternal past and the eternally looping potencies) and, most importantly, the process of creation which is always ongoing and proceeding. For this reason, Schelling conceives of God along the same lines he conceives of Life (God=Life); absolute productivity, or actuality, which is why Life can never be an idea or subsumed by a concept (because it is always developing) or described as a mechanism. It is a process, renewal, or positive becoming that Schelling describes as wirklichkeit. Taking into consideration Schelling’s analogical method from The Ages of the World, God is also a personality – trying to grasp him as just the unconditioned, the absolute, is erroneous as these are concepts that are still from within the domain of negative philosophy. Positive philosophy, for Schelling, must start from being and actual existence (in contrast to negative philosophy that, in Schelling’s eyes, begins with the virtual/shadowy world of the concepts by abstracting from real existence), thus affirming a slight lack of symmetry between being and thought that negative philosophy, whose culmination is in Hegel, cannot conceive of from within its parameters. This is why, among other things, Schelling believes that one needs positive philosophy, but later Schelling’s program was intent on unifying positive philosophy and negative philosophy as a systematic totality.

Asymmetry between Being and Thought

First, why is there an asymmetry between thought and being? To understand this, we must reference Schelling’s The Ages of the World, and the three potencies – the first, negative and contractive potency, the second, positive and outflowing potency, and the unity of the previous two as the third potency. What Schelling is trying to show, through the un-prethinkable act (decision) which can always be seen retroactively, as the beginning of the beginning, is that God longs to be Something and that by actualizing the real, expansive force of the ideal over the negative God can release himself from the looping of the Godhead and create the world. The unprethinkable act is this something that cannot be predicted, conceived, or even seen as something possible within the eternal cycle of the potencies – and yet it is always something that is retroactively realized as having already occurred. This is why The Ages of the World is not only a critique of Hegel’s attempt to arrive at absolute knowing but also of Spinoza’s conception of Divine nature and his necessitarianism. Because there is an irreducible difference between the expansion of God and his dark Ground (in favor of the expansive activity), can there be an actual opposition that within the Godhood was impossible, due to the always recurring collapse of the third potency as the unity of the previous two. Here we can see Schelling’s analogical method at play; like in the quote above, both God and man have to master the darkness inside of them to be able to go into the light. Indeed, it is first God himself who has to undergo this ordeal – for this reason, alone man is his spitting image.

With the above in mind, we’re finally able to see what differentiates Schelling from Hegel’s account of creation (the self-discharge of the Idea into Nature) – whereas Hegel’s account is logical, Schelling conceives of it as a wanting (like in Bohme, where the Nothing wants to be Something). Therefore, Schelling’s viewpoint can be characterized as voluntarist. The reason for this, as we saw in the previous paragraph, is that there is always some facticity, something that Reason can’t grasp – it cannot understand the un-prethinkable act which may seem impossible, and logically is impossible, given the perfect loop of the potencies. It must be an eternal decision that brings an end to the eternal beginning and the eternal end, therefore declaring the beginning of the beginning. What Schelling is grappling with here is the issue of the time before time and how God releases himself out of this perpetuity. For Schelling there can be no logical account of that can encapsulate this. This will be further explored in connection to his critique of Hegel’s Logic.

Because there is an aforementioned asymmetry between being and thought, Schelling claims, there is creation. Otherwise, if there were no differences between being and thought, then everything created and creation as a whole would immediately disappear and cease to exist. As a result, all philosophy, in particular negative, must admit to being incapable of explaining all of reality. Hegel’s philosophy is no exception – what Schelling is particularly rebelling against is the status Hegel is giving to his philosophy as absolute knowing. Any philosophy that claims to be capable of finding the true starting point and from this, through abstract reasoning, develops to the end simply means that this very philosophy is dead. There is no genuine existence within this philosophy – it is merely a philosophy of concepts that purports itself as having discovered the absolute identity of being and thought, but it does this by entirely eradicating actual, living being from this equation and leaving in its stead an empty husk. And as we saw previously, Schelling rejects any philosophy that professes that there is a necessary method at the heart of reality.

Positive and Negative Philosophy

Negative philosophy for Schelling hides away from this startling conclusion; it does not question why are we in Reason at all, or rather why there is Reason at all. By stripping away real, actual existence it does not face the sheer contingency within the heart of being itself. Hegel’s philosophy is for Schelling too formal; it is not able to recognize the inherent unreason within being itself. As Schelling himself says, it is almost fit to say that ”what is rational is what is accidental” (GPP, 99). That’s why for Schelling Hegel’s system is the system of pure reason, and from within pure reason it is capable of arriving to the conclusion of absolute knowing – but there is no reflection upon Reason itself, and the very question of how are we in Reason in the first place. But this cannot be done, because as Schelling claims negative philosophy (Hegel) keeps itself secure within its standpoint by removing actual existence. As we’ll see, and this is Schelling’s key claim, the anxiety of negative philosophy resurfaces at the very end, and the existence it eliminates from its account to keep itself consistent as self-accounting comes to haunt Reason again. As Schelling says:

”Nothing is more comprehensible than the concept, and whoever takes this as the object of their development has chosen the most malleable material. The real concept is only an actus of thinking. What is incomprehensible only begins with that which is opposed to the concept.… Consequently, right from the start, philosophy needs a real opposition.… The world does not consist merely of categories or pure concepts, it does not consist of concrete concepts, but rather of concrete and contingent things, and what is at stake is what is not logical, what is other, which is not the concept, but rather its opposite, which the concept as it were, only unwillingly accepts—this is what is at stake. Here philosophy must pass its test. Hic Rhodus, hic salta.” (GPP, 225)

So what is at stake? The philosophy that is to come and correct negative philosophy (Hegel) must rectify the mistake of removing everything real and living so that it arrives at the structure of the development of the logical Concept. Because of this two problems for Schelling particularly stick out in Hegel: the beginning and the very ending. The problem of the beginning only becomes retrospectively apparent however. First, we must look at the ending for Schelling.

The end of Hegel’s Logic

By abstracting from all actual being and existence, the logical concept seems to develop finely for Schelling. Led by an impulse for ever greater comprehensiveness, which is the first charge he levies at Hegel – the development is not immanent as Hegel claims it is, but because the structure is logical it only demands even further mediation, even further comprehensive development – the dialectic remains rather consistent until the very end. In the end, however, the movement completely breaks off and the dialectic that Hegel relied upon, or professed to be the very immanent movement of the structure itself, is no more. Why? Here’s what Schelling says:

”The self-movement of the concept… held out as long as the system advanced through logical space, but as soon as it had to make the difficult step into reality the path of the dialectical movement broke off totally (my emphasis). A second hypothesis becomes necessary, namely, that the idea – one knows not why, unless to interrupt the boredom (my emphasis) of its merely logical existence – allows its moments to fall apart, so that through them nature could arise. The first presupposition of the philosophy that allegedly presupposes nothing was thus that the pure logical concept has the property or nature, of itself (since the subjectivity of the philosopher should be excluded), to change into its opposite (to, so to speak, overthrow itself), to again change back into itself; a deed that one can think of a real, living being, but of a mere concept one can neither think nor imagine, but can only assert (my emphasis). The breaking off of the Idea, that is, of the perfected concept, from itself, was the second fiction since this transition is no longer a dialectical transition, but of a different sort, for which it would be difficult to find a name, for which in a purely rational system there is no such category, and for which even the creator him self in his system has no category (my emphasis). The attempt to go back to the standpoint of the scholastics…and to begin metaphysics with a pure rational concept that excludes everything empirical and then later to introduce the previously rejected empirical nature through the backdoor of the Idea becoming different or untrue to itself: this episode in the history of modern philosophy…, has at least served to demonstrate anew that it is impossible to get at reality (reality = wirklichkeit – we mentioned this term before when inquiring into Schelling’s God or Life) through a pure philosophy of reason (my emphasis; I/10, 212-213).

Let’s explain the quote piece by piece. First, what Schelling is talking about in the beginning – the dialectical movement breaking off totally when it had to step into reality – is the end of the Logic in Hegel, namely the self-discharge of the Absolute Idea into Nature (return to Life). Next, when he mentions boredom of the Idea; Schelling’s usage of boredom is explicitly important because Schelling here wants to underline how much logical development is stripped of actual life, no matter the Hegelian characterizations of the life immanent in the very development of the logical structure – Schelling would emphasize that this is not true life. He also wants to show how much Hegel is cheating when he thinks that Logic can birth Life. Schelling also obviously disagrees with Hegel’s characterizations at the end of the Logic that the Absolute Idea is absolute life. Then Schelling mentions two fictions: the first one being that the concept can go back into itself after changing into its opposite – what Schelling wants to emphasize is that the very movement Hegel conceived of is not wrong, but that it cannot be predicated of concepts as Hegel does in his eyes. The second fiction, which we mentioned at the beginning of this paragraph, is the self-discharge of the Idea into Nature. For Schelling this is no longer indicative of the dialectical movement which is present throughout the Hegelian Logic – in fact, for Schelling, it is something that Hegel himself cannot recognize within the Logic and for which he has no name or category. Therefore Hegelian Logic is the best proof, even more than Fichte’s Sciences of Knowing which also belongs to negative philosophy, that one cannot arrive to Life through merely the logical Concept. It is only through this failure of the negative philosophy that positive philosophy is born.

What Schelling is particularly protesting against in Hegel is the question that he evades to describe the self-discharge of the Idea into Nature – and that is the question of ”time before time” – the eternal past. What this means is the following: Schelling’s goal in The Ages of the World, mentioned at the beginning, is to pose the following question – how does God emerge from eternity for there to be time at all? This is a question that also directly concerns Hegel, given that Logic does take place within this realm as well. Schelling conceives of this past not as a past present (something that used to be now, but has passed away and is no longer) but as the eternal past, which is a dimension of time that can never be connected to a present ”now” and utterly precedes the empirical past as we know it. This past is the ground of the present, that in which God himself was immersed as Godhood, which is also the true a priori instead of the Hegelian Logic. What Schelling wants to show is that the true a priori is this eternal past that cannot be conceived within a logical system because it is the fullness of being. Hegel, because he eradicates actual existence, is capable of imitating something akin to this eternal past through Logic, given that Logic, as a transcendental ontology, takes place before time. But Hegel is mistaken for Schelling because Hegel doesn’t fully acknowledge that this very dimension of time is the true a priori. This also explains the ”un-prethinkable act” that was mentioned earlier; in this eternal past, past, present and as a result, the future are all joined together – there is no separation between them, because of the eternally looping potencies and the always collapsing unity of the third potency. God decides to end this eternal past and get out of his Godhood, – and this is the un-prethinkable act – it is the act, the decision because the looping is perfect, and there is no indication that God will get out of this quagmire of the Godhood; which is also why it is unprethinkable! – to separate the present from the past and the past from the present. This is God’s free decision (which is why The Ages of the World is a critique of Spinoza – separation between the Godhead as God’s necessary nature and God’s free agency). This decision of course is therefore indicative of the radical contingency that is expressive of authentic freedom – to decide that enough is enough, that the ”time” has come – this can only be done by mastering the dark ground within oneself. This is the true a priori – not the Logic of Hegel, but the eternal past from which the true beginning may truly begin. What Hegel did not acknowledge, again, is this very dimension of ”temporality” itself. This is why Schelling criticizes Hegel’s return to Life – it does not demonstrate freedom at all since it eliminates being itself and reduces God to logic.

For Schelling, Hegel inverts the order of existence – the order of subject’s reflexive concept of being is asserted over the extra-logical (extra-logical because it is the ground of Reason) ground of real, existing nature. Schelling would claim that Hegel’s proof of the groundlessness of the Hegelian Logic is even further proof of how it inverts everything upside down. This is why Hegel proves only the identity of the concept of being with the idea. Late Schelling in 1852 will himself conceive that negative philosophy itself is a necessary part of the systematic totality which comprises of both negative and positive philosophy – but the crux of the matter is that negative philosophy on its own has no legs to stand with and, most importantly, that it is unaware of this. Hegel’s beginning with Pure Being is nothing else than a concept that excludes everything else. We’ve mentioned how Hegel eradicates all existence, to begin with what Schelling calls the empty concept of being – and now, to connect this point to the problem of beginning we’ve mentioned previously in connection with the problem of ending – this very concept of being presupposed true being as that which is latent of the concept’s reflection. Reflection is not what comes first, that’s nature – but Hegel in Schelling’s eyes accidentally (or deliberately) forgets this, which is the sole reason why he can come to absolute knowing and the Absolute Idea but which itself is also false, as we’ve seen for Schelling when the issue of the self-discharge is raised. This is why the category of ”release” is indicative of a movement that is no longer familiar, and in fact, breaks Hegel’s immanence – Hegel forces the issue because he otherwise knows that there is no reason why would the Idea externalize itself into something less perfect than it (since Nature is the mixture of Reason and unReason and is not free like the Absolute Idea is).

Furthermore, Schelling rejects any explanation of this movement that would emphasize that the discharge of the Absolute Idea is the Idea proving that it is free by externalizing itself. Schelling would ask, as he did in his History of Modern Philosophy – to whom is it proving itself? To itself? If that is the case, no need, because it already knows it is perfect and free. To the philosopher? If so, then it is clear that Hegel is forcing the issue because he otherwise recognizes that there is a problem. If this is true, then we must accept the patently absurd conclusion that the Absolute Idea discharges itself to prove itself to an empirically existing individual. And if we emphasize that it does, as Hegel himself says, in a self-satisfied manner and assured of itself – Schelling would immediately state that Hegel is cheating here by inserting Life into the system of Logic whose entire premise, as we’ve seen in Schelling’s account, bases itself on eradication of alive existence and being. Schelling would claim that this is, as he does in the quote above, reintroducing the empirical nature through the backdoor of the Idea. In other words, it utterly breaks the dialectical movement of the Logic. Hegel has no answer to the problem of the beginning because he does not acknowledge what the ground of his system is. But this ground cannot be admitted if we only take Reason’s word as self-accounting. In other words, Hegel is far too dogmatic – he merely asserts Reason.

Self-relating Negation

So why does Hegel feel the necessity, as Schelling thinks, to reintroduce Life through the backdoor of the Idea? Let’s go back to the issue of the beginning of Hegel’s Logic. Schelling believes that before he initiates the negation out of which Pure Being emerges as a result, he does presuppose something. What this means is that when Hegel asserts that Pure Being is pure immediacy (it is not conditioned by any determination, i.e. it is unconditioned) he must likewise posit that the Nothing is the same, else there would be an asymmetry between being and thought, which is contrary to Hegel’s goal. But Hegel already presupposes one thing – intuition.

One can only comprehend a single, immediate being through intuition. Schelling would deny Hegel’s explanation that this is an expression of reflection’s negation of its self-relation because that is nothing more than an inversion of the existing order of things. Schelling would also likewise deny the validity of the logical movement in Pure Being = Nothing -> Becoming. For Hegel, negation’s capability of self-reference (or autonomy) makes possible the creation of a result that is different from the initial starting point – Pure Being had already vanished, and the truth of it is Becoming – the return is to a position that is the truth of the preceding nothingness (or pure immediacy) and differentiates itself from it. Therefore there is the difference that is generated through negation’s self-reference, which is the crux of the immanent movement in Hegel. It is only at the end, through the positing of presuppositions, that the Absolute Idea, which is free, is revealed as having been also in the first moment as immediate being. The Absolute Idea is, after all, the absolute identity of thought and being; each moment, including the beginning and the end, is a finite determination and is itself the image of the Absolute. There being, and existence is guaranteed retroactively through the realization of God as the Absolute Idea. That is the Hegelian intellectual intuition. The Absolute Idea, because it is self-positing, posits itself as having been presupposed all along – as already having been.

Schelling’s problem with this view, however, is that it conflates that which is the ground and that which is grounded. If the truth of original, immediate pure Being is revealed through the return of the Absolute Idea as that which is the essence of pure Being, to it as having been its essence all along, then for Schelling, we have no way of establishing the criterion through which we could prove that the absolute identity is the essence of the original unmediated being, since this very original being itself is utterly indeterminate. This is why Schelling criticizes Hegel on the count of not being immanent as he claimed his philosophy to be – driven by ever greater comprehensiveness, he is incapable of establishing the difference between the ground and the grounded because Hegel can only conceive of the grounded as being the ground by eliminating the ground out of the equation due to its lesser determinacy in comparison to the higher determinacy, or in this case, the highest determinacy. If we have pure indeterminacy and the Absolute Idea articulating itself as the truth of this indeterminacy, we lose not only the ground but the grounded itself. For Schelling therefore, the only consistent position here is that this very truth returning to its first moment to demonstrate to have been the truth of this original experience must therefore negate itself so that it becomes the first moment again to prove to have been the truth of this moment because the first moment, since it is utterly indeterminate, cannot be the criterion of this truth – but this would only mean that the very demonstration of having been the truth of the first moment all along would dissipate. For there to be Truth, Truth has to be negated and return to the first position, thereby restarting the dialectic anew all over again, since the Truth would be forgotten again in the first moment – recall that Schelling thought that the Hegelian movement can only be predicated of living beings and not logical concepts; this is what happens, according to Schelling, when you do predicate it of concepts. Because of this, it would be an eternal cycle or a loop that would never be able to escape from itself – just like what Schelling describes in the Ages of the World. This is why Schelling thought Hegel felt the necessity to include in the ”release” of the Idea into Nature – precisely to avoid this conclusion, which is the logical ending to his enterprise since he removed all actual existence. But we’ve also seen that this ”release” has no place within the dialectical development, which only proves that Logic cannot explain Life. For Schelling, therefore, Hegel cheats at the very end – it is this very failure itself that must give birth to positive philosophy.

Immanence

This is why Schelling criticizes him, on Kantian grounds, for having forgotten that all negation presupposes a positive reality and that predicates must have their common ground in something transcendent to them, which alone can be the criterion, which we’ve seen in Hegel is lacking, through which one can judge their agreement and difference.

To approach the issue of the self-discharge again having in mind Schelling’s need for a transcendent ground, the problem Schelling finds in, to use the example of Logic of Being and Logic of Essence now, is that because negated being is always shown to be the ground and yet having its truth in essence, through which negated being dissociates into two relata, these relata are themselves non-being because the truth of their being in essence, as the correlate, is prioritized rather than their being-ness; the grounded becomes the ground by reducing the ground to non-being itself (Matthews, 2007). We’ve seen how this circle occurs in the previous section concerning Absolute Idea-Pure being. Now, Schelling asks, if negation does presuppose being in this way, which is nothing more than relative non-being, or at worst, complete nothing, then the Absolute Idea’s self-discharge into Nature is impossible since there’s nothing in which the Absolute Idea may discharge itself into. Worse yet, this means that God himself has no being.

Let us draw the example Schelling himself uses. Since Nature is that which comes after Logic, Schelling is particularly interested in the fact that the realized Idea is therefore at the limit of Logic, and so has Nature completely outside of it. But Nature must be equally a priori as well. What Schelling wants to emphasize is that the nature that is to come after the end of Logic is not this a priori nature, since itself it is not present in Logic. But how else is the Logic supposed to transition to Nature? Furthermore, if we accept Hegel’s thesis that Nature is the agony of the Concept (meaning that Nature is the break with the Idea) and that through Nature as a result the Concept becomes something untrue to itself due to Nature, then there can be only opposition between the logical and the natural. But there is no reason, if there is no a priori nature within the Logic, for the Idea to discharge itself into Nature since this consists of a radical break of its perfect freedom. Why would the Idea do this, which is conscious of itself as the Real-Ideal and is ”impenetrable atomic individuality, but explicitly universality and cognition, and in its other has its objectivity for its object”?

For Schelling, therefore, Hegel becomes conscious of the ”negativity of this end” and the force of the positive which demands that the Idea steps out of its logical space. Schelling’s proof for this is the fact that there is a paragraph in the Encyclopedia, where Hegel says that the ”Idea purifies itself of all appearance of happening, of contingency and of the being-outside and being-in-succession of the moments (the content of the Idea still has this appearance in religion, which pulls the content apart into a temporal and external sequence just so it can be imagined)” (HoMP, 157). What Schelling wants to show is how Hegel is coming close to his view that we explained in the Ages of the World – of the very dimension of temporality that Schelling emphasizes is the true a priori.

Hegel did not stop there according to Schelling. The second edition of Logic had a much more interesting passage that implicated for Schelling that Hegel was slowly coming to realize that the positive was necessary. ”The Last, into which everything goes as into its ground, is then also that from which the First, which was initially established as something immediate, emerges, and ”in this way the absolute spirit, which results as the concrete and last, the highest truth of all being is known as externalizing itself with freedom and as releasing itself into the form of an immediate being at the end of the development – as resolving itself to the creation of a world which contains everything which fell into the development which had preceded that result, so that all this (everything which preceded in the development) is transformed along with its beginning, via this reversed position, into something which is dependent upon the result as a principle (my emphasis)” ” (HoMP, 157)

Schelling notes here what was mentioned earlier – the beginning which led to the Absolute became something dependent on the result retroactively and the result itself becomes the principle that the prior beginning was. Now recall that we mentioned that Schelling thought Hegel’s movement is not wrong – but that its mistake consists in being predicated on concepts, which we explored in several paragraphs before. We’ve come back full circle – What Schelling is saying here is that this is exactly the right move and he adds that, if this reversal was possible, Hegel would have not only the negative philosophy but also positive philosophy side-by-side in a harmonious unity. What he would have to recognize at that point, according to Schelling, is that negative philosophy, due to only having the hypothetical passage to Nature, must be subordinated and complemented by positive philosophy. And this Hegel could not do, because his identity philosophy was unclear on one thing. For Schelling, that is the fact that one cannot state and try to demonstrate, as Hegel does, ”that in the Last everything goes as into its ground; one ought rather say: everything preceding grounded itself by the fact that it lowers itself to being the ground of what follows, i.e. to that which is no longer itself being but is instead the ground of being for another (recall here the issue of the non-being of the ground described above) it grounds itself by its going-to-ground, it is ground thereby, not what follows (HMoP, 158).” It is that which falls which finds its ground by being the ground of something higher than itself. Only in this way, for Schelling, ”…everything finally grounds itself by the fact that it subordinates itself as a ground to the Absolute, to the Last”. Positive philosophy is nothing more but a way to correct the mistakes of Hegel’s Logic.

Here it should become rather obvious that Schelling’s positive philosophy is in many ways a reaction to what he perceived as Hegel’s failure. Since Schelling believed that Hegel opted that the end becomes the beginning only after it is revealed as the end (as Hegel himself says, the ultimate goal of all philosophy is the reconciliation of Thought and the world, but this can only be realized retrospectively), the whole movement up to the Last is, therefore, nothing more than an ”uninterrupted… succession of final causes; each in its place is just as much final… for what precedes it as the Last is final cause for everything”. It is here where the absurdity of the Hegelian system becomes blatantly obvious, and the inversion of worlds is at its peak – if organic nature is the final cause of inorganic nature, and in organic nature, the animal is the final cause of the plant, and humankind itself is the final cause of the animal world; then it is also true, according to Hegel, through the reversal that Hegel commits to described above, that humankind is also the effective and productive cause of the animal realm! This would be no problem if we took Hegel’s claim that the truth of the animal realm is retrospectively the human realm – but we’ve seen that when this is done the ground becomes the non-ground. What is required here, according to Schelling, is the true reversal described above – the ground itself grounds itself by going to ground; by becoming the ground of the other. This movement itself implies that a radically different outlook is needed.

Less abstractly, the issue for Schelling is that there is no witness after the removal of the externality and the positing of Nature by the Idea that the Idea was originally in the first position, which we’ve explained that it retroactively was. Because the Hegelian process consistently swaps the ground with the grounded thereby reducing the former to non-being, there is no proof that the Absolute Idea was at the beginning – because it removed the original proof in favor of showing its truth because of its indeterminacy. But by doing this, Hegel is for Schelling inconsistent and shows how much he is not immanent at all but wants only even more comprehensiveness – the problem of the beginning is shown only through the ending. If Hegel is to be consistent it is the original abstract being that must do the talking and the grounding to the Absolute. But since it was removed as an externality, due to its pure immediacy, the Absolute Idea thereby loses the necessary grounding from which it could build its existence retroactively. But since it is pure immediacy, Hegel has to avoid the first loop we mentioned above – since it is conceived the way it is, any proof of the Truth is lost since the return to the original position results in its negation (due to the pure indeterminacy or the original being). Because Hegel has reduced it to non-being and then illegitimately raised it to be as Nature (in other words, the positing of Nature at the end is completely inconsistent according to Schelling, because, as we’ve seen in the movement of self-relating negation, there is no logical consistency in suddenly giving the Absolute Idea this power that hasn’t been demonstrated), God only has hypothetically necessary being, not in actuality.

It is for this reason that Hegel’s philosophy, for Schelling, remains only the philosophy of the logical concept – a merely logical idea of God. Because there is no actual being in this system of logic, even if God is proven to be necessary, and Schelling granted Hegel that he did prove that God is a necessary idea, he did not prove that he has existence Schelling’s viewpoint on the Hegelian system is that Hegel arrived to the Absolute Idea which explicitly cannot exist. Not only this, but since it cannot exist, then it is merely an un-actualized necessity; in which case the self-discharge of the Idea into Nature, if we remove from the view the impossibility of this action, only proves how much God is not free. The action is purely formal; since the Absolute can do nothing but suffer in nature since Hegel conceived it in that way – instead of being expressive of God’s free agency, God has to carry the world on its back like Atlas, condemned by his necessity. To illustrate the problem of this let’s go back to the recurring problem of the perpetual loop; since the Idea out of necessity self-discharges itself into Nature and suffers in it, it will keep doing this all over again. In the previous example the example of looping was used without the self-discharge of the Idea – but, if we do hypothetically grant that this does occur, then the same problem reappears again. The idea that can only suffer in Nature will relieve itself of this suffering by becoming the perfect Idea once more, only to discharge itself into Nature once more because of a necessity, suffer again, self-discharge again, and so in perpetuity…

And if we grant that this occurs because the Idea knows it will not lose itself in Nature, then Nature is nothing free, but simply a playground for the necessary Idea which, knowing that it won’t perish, in a play of solipsism, literally generates the opposite (Nature) so it can emerge triumphant over it – an even worse version of the Fichtean non-I (which was at least in Fichte posited as a result of the I’s radical finitude!). Of course, in a system like this, for Schelling, there can only be necessity and no freedom, mechanism, and no organic development. The Hegelian system knows that there must be the externalization of the Idea into Nature, but this Nature constantly remains something foreign or an obstacle to the Idea – ironically, Schelling raises the same kind of criticism Hegel himself used when speaking of Protestant consciousness and reflexive philosophies of subjectivity in Faith and Knowledge (one could say that Schelling’s criticism is that of a Hegelian inversion against Hegel himself!). As a result, the Hegelian system can admit of no positive element and it maintains itself on this basis by thinking that the only refutation possible is if one criticizes it internally. But this itself is the disease of the Hegelian system for Schelling. By refusing real being, it has already set the stakes in a game in an inverted world it’s always going to win, but because its Truth can only be demonstrated through the negation of this same Truth, this game will repeat itself indefinitely. From this Schelling concludes that the only way beyond the pitfalls of the Hegelian Logic’s own making is by conceiving Logic and Naturphilosophie as one.

Conclusion

The problem with the Hegelian System is that it has never considered that there must be a real other to the necessity of Reason. Because Hegel only sees Reason generating its Other, Reason never faces the anxiety that results from the encounter with something that is truly Other to it. In Hegel’s philosophy, Reason is hiding subconsciously, although it does not know from what, and yet, even when it has assured itself an absolute victory, it is incapable of actually stopping the game itself. The hegelian system can admit to no openness, no future; in an ironic twist to the Hegelian system, the victor, the absolute Idea, becomes the vanquished and vice versa, and this cycle repeats itself endlessly. The idea is in the same position as the Godhood in the eternal past that is described in The Ages of the World, eternally re-constituting and collapsing in itself and vice versa, because there is absolute equality between the first two potencies. Schelling’s late project is no irrational mysticism as some Hegelians think; it is inspired by a real logical problem that Hegel, for Schelling, was unable to resolve. What positive philosophy must do is go beyond this Hegelian deadlock, it must be able to think of the act which Logic alone is incapable of. To do so, it must first take heed of that which was removed from the Hegelian tale – Nature itself.

Hegel’s Early Critique of Kant

Hegel’s Faith and Knowledge represents one of the major contributions to the Critical Journal in which Hegel was co-editor with Schelling. Published in July 1802 as the only essay of the first issue of the second volume, it represents a watershed in Hegel’s thought. The original title Hegel gave to this work was “The Kant-Jacobi-Fichtean Philosophy”, with the title page explaining that the author would wholly deal with the “reflective philosophy of subjectivity in the complete range of its forms as Kantian, Jacobian and Fichtean philosophy”. As it will turn out, Hegel will situate the manifestations of these reflective philosophies within an overarching cultural critique of Protestantism.

First, some word about the journal itself. The word about creating a scientific-philosophical journal had been around from 1798, but it only gained steam in 1800 when Schelling asked of the publisher Johann Friedrich Cotta to assist him in realizing such an enterprise. Schelling made the suggestion to Fichte that they should edit it together, and Fichte accepted the offer, who himself had entertained ideas about a journal independent of Schelling and Cotta. It was during this time, from 1800 to 1801, that Hegel himself was immersed in Fichte’s own works, an effort which will ultimately culminate in the Difference essay.  

However, the original plan was not realized for a number of reasons. Leaving aside the atheism controversy Fichte was embroiled in, there were theoretical disagreements (Fichtean criticism of Schelling’s Absolute, Schelling’s criticism of Fichte’s one-sided view of Nature) as well as personal (Schelling’s private insults, Fichte’s uncharitable interpretations despite Schelling’s direct explanations of the problematic passages)  – their correspondence between 1800 to 1802 shows that the once friendly relationship was no more, in part, thanks to Hegel himself and the publication of the Difference essay. Here it must be remarked that while the Difference essay was successful in pointing out the clear divergences between Fichte and Schelling, some of which Schelling and Fichte were unaware of up to that point, the two philosophers, albeit awkwardly, were already aware prior to that that their respective paths were irreconcilable. The essay solidified Hegel’s continued collaboration with Schelling and it served as a blueprint for the Faith and Knowledge essay as well.

Introduction

The introduction begins with a dichotomy that is the lynch-pin of the entire work: faith and knowledge. Hegel states that his time had risen above the “ancient antithesis” of Reason and Faith since the opposition between the two was transferred to the domain of philosophy itself (the age of Enlightenment). No longer the handmaid of faith, as it was during the Middle Ages, Reason asserted its absolute autonomy and proved that Faith’s miracles and its “positive” elements (dogma and superstitious beliefs) were null and void. The Enlightentment was victorious in dispelling the falsehoods of religion, proving Reason’s power. Here, however, Hegel notes that this victory might not have been a victory after all, because what Reason fought against was, in his analysis, a limited conception of Faith that Reason created in order to make the opposition, and enlightened Reason’s own identity in this opposition, meaningful. This is explained by analogy: Reason has suffered the same fate that barbarians suffer after they triumph over civilized nations – they take over them and become their rulers, but they eventually assimilate and succumb to those same conquered nations spiritually – in other words, they are defeated from inside out. The end-result of Reason’s struggle is that it realized that the positive elements which it took to be the essence of Faith were in reality not what Faith was; and that because of this, not only “Faith”, the opponent, but also the very conception enlightened Reason had of itself that it formed through this struggle, had in fact never existed to begin with. For Hegel, this state of affairs resulted into:

“The new born peace that hovers triumphantly over the corpse of Reason and faith, uniting them as the child of both, has as little of Reason in it as it has of authentic faith” (F&K, 55)

            This “new born peace” uniting the corpses of Reason and Faith, are “reflective philosophies of subjectivity”, i.e. Kantian, Jacobian and Fichtean.

What Hegel means by this is that these philosophies are the result of Reason’s coming back to itself after cognizing the vacuousness of its victory. In other words, having believed in its own absolute freedom, meaning that it took itself as self-determining and independent from anyone else, including Faith,  Reason used its critical powers to dispel the falsehoods of Faith. If something is to be true, it must be true according to the laws of Reason, which are its own laws – there is no external law that Reason can admit other than its own. Faith’s mysteries and miracles stipulated that its truths are beyond the domain of Reason. In having emerged as victorious, however, Reason realized that it cannot supply any positive knowledge of God on its own without refuting itself or falling into antinomies. The truth of the ‘’absolute autonomy’’ and self-determination it took itself to be,  conceptions which it formed through the opposition with Faith, was nothing but the power of Reason as critique.  It is only after the battle that it retrospectively realizes that  it can say nothing substantial about the eternal. Because of this, Reason realizes that all of its knowledge is in fact accidental and finite, because it is outside the eternal which it cannot cognize (and it cannot accept the old dogmas of Faith as a possible method of accessing it either). Since knowledge is nullified from inside out, the only refuge is, ironically, in Faith, but now reconceived as something outside and above Reason itself, transcending Reason – as a Beyond (we will see this term more often). 

Already in Faith and Knowledge, therefore, we see the dialectical inversion that would become more prominent in Phenomenology and Logic –  declaring independence and freedom from Faith, Reason, through its battle against Faith, only ended up being the handmaid of Faith once again. This time, however, not by acquiesing to its dogmas or miracles, which was formerly taken to be the essence of Faith, but by willingly accepting that true knowledge can only be in a Beyond. The wedge between Reason and Faith persists, with the victor becoming the vanquished and the vanquished becoming the victor. Reason fully submits to Faith once more – the proof of this movement, especially in Germany, are the philosophies of Kant, Jacobi and Fichte.

This is why Hegel believes that the core of the Enlightenment is a “hubbub of vanity without a firm core” (F&K, 56) – the power of its critique is infinite, and yet all knowledge it can actually admit is finite – i.e. knowledge only of this world. The Enlightenment, in turn, declared that man doesn’t need to know the infinite, or partake in God’s knowledge and life. The infinite exists, but it is not something that human Reason can grasp (Kant). This is the Enlightenment’s way of reconciling man to this world. It does this at the expense of conceiving the infinite, the Beyond, as something implicitly (or, as we will see in the case of Protestantism, explicitly) superior to this world. However, the truth of this infinity as a perfect Beyond is that it is nothing more than a finite infinity – Reason, as finite, can never be incorporated within this infinite, and the infinite likewise is limited, since finite Reason can never cognize it and because of this is doomed to remain outside of it. This is why Hegel states that the truth of the Enlightenment is the negative – it is finitude at its purest. The finite that remains outside of infinity, and an infinity that is actually finite, are, because the finite by nature is accidental, nothing. Hegel dismissed the Enlightenment because it made this nothingness into a system. It does not truly resolve the question of God and leaves the reconciliation incomplete.

            This is the point at which Faith & Knowledge becomes a cultural critique, because Hegel states that, from the religious point of view, the principle of Enlightenment is also the principle of Protestantism. It is here where the problem of the Enlightenment becomes explicit. Here it is worth quoting the full passage in question:

“Religion builds its temples and altars in the heart of the individual. In sighs and prayers he seeks for the God whom he denies to himself in intuition, because of the risk that the intellect will cognize what is intuited as a mere thing, reducing the sacred grove to mere timber. Of course, the inner must be externalized; intention must become effective in action; immediate religious sentiment must be expressed in external gesture; and faith, though it flees from the objectivity of cognition, must become objective to itself in thoughts, concepts, and words. But the intellect scrupulously distinguishes the objective from the subjective, and the objective is what is accounted worthless and null. The struggle of subjective beauty must be directed precisely to this end: to defend itself properly against the necessity through which the subjective becomes objective. That beauty should become real in objective form, and fall captive to objectivity, that consciousness should seek to be directed at exposition and objectivity themselves, that it should want to shape appearance or, shaped in it, to be at home there-all this should cease; for it would be a dangerous superfluity, and an evil, as the intellect could turn it into a thing (zu einem Etwas)

            Here is an another inversion at play. Earlier it was remarked that the Enlightenment’s reconciliation amounted to the claim that there is no need to have the knowledge of the eternal – reconciliation is knowing this world, and this is the standpoint of enlightened Reason. Within the domain of Protestantism, however, this attitude gives birth to subjectivities of longing. Since the finite = nothing, that which is necessary, the infinite, the Divine must be a perfection beyond this world and Reason’s comprehension. On the other hand, the subject is aware that it cannot access God through commandments or miracles – the elements it previously worked hard to refute. Reason rebels against anything which would portray itself as true and yet hide its essence and characterize it as something mysterious beyond Reason’s grasp. This is, after all, why enlightened Reason fought to refute the superstitions and the supposed miracles – because it saw they were vacuous concepts. But it is precisely here where the problem resides. Something is true insofar as it is objectified – meaning, the truth cannot hide itself. Intellect therefore knows that the inward must be externalised, intention must be actualized, faith must become objective to itself in thoughts. But because the objective world is finite, all knowledge of it, including the world itself, since it is opposed to a perfect Beyond, are worthless. Therefore this subjectivity finds itself in a contradiction – one knows that the truth of intentions and faith not only reside in them having been felt, but also actualized in the objective world, but because the objective world is worthless, they are rendered into things and their worth is diminished as a result of it.  Actualizing them, externalizing them, from the purview of Protestant consciousness, is evil. This Protestant consciousness will give birth to the reflexive philosophies that are the theme of Hegel’s text. And as we saw, the Reason which previously fought to eliminate the vacuous concepts of Faith clad in the robes of miracles and mysteries, now fully accepts the Beyond which likewise cannot be conceptualized.

If we go back to the Enlightenment, Hegel’s problem is that it absolutizes the empirical instead of the other pole of the antithesis, the Beyond – however, the immersion into the empirical, or reconciliation with ordinary life for Hegel is a fall into a vulgar eudaemonism. The only upshot is the Enlightenment’s striving toward ,,justification and good conscience”.   But if the Absolute is transformed into the empirical, Reason cannot truly achieve reconciliation nor justify its striving. As Hegel says, only the objectivity of the intellect (intellect which is externalized) can attain the concept, which has presented itself in its most highly abstract form as so-called pure Reason (which is the standpoint of reflexive philosophies). This is why he favors Kant, Jacobi and Fichte to the philosophers of Enlightenment, like Hume.

Because of the focus on the empirical, the Enlightenment doesn’t actually realize that when it declares ,,happiness” as the Idea, and this entails immersion into the empirical world, this very same happiness, conceived as the Idea (or the Absolute) is something no longer empirical and sensuous, but abstract. From the standpoint of absolute knowing, the Idea is:

”If the highest bliss is the highest Idea, it is the union between infinite and finite – rational action and feeling. Both of these things are contained within the Idea – the highest Idea cannot be, as the highest being (Dasein), if there is no unity between the two. When Reason cognizes this, these two things in unity, both of these moments vanish and are absorbed into one another. ” The Enlightenment separates one pole from the other – it emphasizes feeling – so it only knows sensual and not ,,the bliss of eternal vision”, which is the unity of feeling and rational action. On the other hand, the culmination of Protestant alienation are the reflexive philosophies which, as we will see later on in Kantian and Fichtean philosophies, emphasize rational action at the expense of feeling.

Philosophies of Reflexive Subjectivities

With all of this in mind, we can approach the criticism of Kant, Jacobi and Fichte. Hegel identifies certain elements that are common to all of these philosophies, whose roots we’ve explored in the previous section.

All of these philosophies take the finite as absolute. It is in and for itself, and it is the sole reality accessible to Reason. Because of this, the infinite and finite are not posited as identical in the Idea, like the aforementioned rational action and feeling are; they are opposed to one another ”in a connection of domination” (F&K, 60). Therefore, the reconciling ”middle term”, which is the third between the two is not present in reflexive philosophies of subjectivity, but is always something beyond Reason which is sundered across two poles (a spurious infinity and finitude). For this reason, the Absolute is absolute emptiness of Reason, faith into the incomprehensible (F&K, 61). This absolute emptiness present in Kantian, Fichtean and Jacobian philosophies is also perfect abstraction – which the Enlightenment was unable to achieve.

To explicate this point even further – Hegel is claiming that the Enlightenment failed in achieving the standpoint of pure thinking, the concept. This absolute abstraction from all empirical content is necessary. Because it was unable to do this, since its Idea was still in part empirical, the opposition between the infinite and finite is not as absolute as it is in philosophies of reflexive subjectivities (it is still implicit). The true opposition that appears in the reflexive philosophies (which are the culmination of what Hegel criticized in the Protestant consciousness) is between the Concept and the empirical – between thought and the world. The empirical is negativity for the concept, the concept is negativity for the empirical, and the concept itself is negative (F&K, 62). As we saw in Hegel’s depiction of Protestant consciousness, the inward is opposed to the external, because the external cannot compare to that which is inward. The Idea, the totality and the unity of the Concept and empirical, remains undiscovered. However, it is only in these philosophies that reflection becomes possible – namely, in absolute opposition. This is why Hegel states:

”The fundamental principle common to the philosophies of Kant, Jacobi and Fichte is, then, the absoluteness of finitude and, resulting from it, the absolute antithesis of finitude and infinity, reality and ideality, the sensuous and the supersensuous, and the beyondness of what is truly real and absolute. Within this common ground, however, these philosophies form antitheses among themselves, exhausting the totatity of possible forms of this principle

            Here it must be remarked that Hegel thinks that that oppositions, or dualisms, are necessary, but they are not the final word. Even if the Idea or the totality remains unknown to these philosophies, from the standpoint of absolute knowing it is to their credit that they, even if they failed in grasping it, nonetheless carved a path to the Idea as the unity of the Concept and the empirical, precisely because they reduced the both poles of the antithesis to their purity. This point will be made further clear in Hegel’s depiction of Kant’s philosophy.  Kant postulated that the absolute concept is practical Reason, existing strictly for itself. Kant’s objectivity becomes subjectivity in Jacobi – the antithesis between the finite and the infinite is transposed into feeling of Reason, and Reason is infinitely longing and grieving. Fichtean striving is obligatory and infinite, never to end in personal self-fulfillment. (F&K, 62) In Hegel’s eyes they are still within the domain of Enlightenment’s eudaemonism, as much as they are opposed to its emphasis on ordinary life by opting for rational action (especially Kant and Fichte, less so Jacobi). They simply chose the other pole of the antithesis, but this did not solve the problem, nor effect a genuine reconciliation. Described as the systematization of the culture of reflection described above in Protestantism, they remained stuck to bad infinity.

“For this infinite is itself not the truth since it is unable to consume and consummate finitude…If the absolute were put together out of the finite and the infinite, abstracting from the finite would indeed be a loss. In the Idea, however, finite and infinite are one, and hence finitude as such, i.e., as something that was supposed to have truth and reality in and for itself, has vanished. Yet what was negated was only the negative in finitude; and thus the true affirmation was posited.” (F&K, 65-66)

Kantian Philosophy

            One of the things Hegel commends Kant for is for being forthright. At the beginning of his critique he states:

“Because the essence of the Kantian philosophy consists in its being critical idealism, it plainly confesses that its principle is subjectivism and formal thinking. Secure in its standpoint, which makes the unity of reflection supreme, it reveals what it is and aims at, by telling its story quite frankly. The name of Reason which it gives to the Concept may, at the worst, impede the disclosure or mask it. “

            For Hegel, Kant confesses that his ultimate standpoint is that of being a subjectivist. Within the first Critique the highest Idea in Kant is something that is absolutely empty – nothing can be said of the thing-in-itself, and all possible knowledge is finite. Within the “final stage of development”, Kant does establish the highest Idea, but this Idea is something that merely has subjective, and not objective necessity – this highest Idea Kant can grasp is the Practical Reason, which remains separate from the world of phenomena and lies in the noumenal world. Because the phenomenal and noumenal selves are separated and situated respectively in the world of causality and world of freedom, Kant’s philosophy remains within the antithesis between the empirical and freedom.

               There is merit in Kant’s philosophy, however. Its merit lies in the fact that it cognizes that the Concept cannot remain in isolation from anything that is intuitied and vice versa. It recognizes the importance of experience – intuition by itself is blind and the concept by itself is empty (CPR: A 51, B 75). But because it is confined to experience and opposes it to an unknowable Beyond, the noumenal, it remains absolute finitude.  The direction Kant had chosen to adopt is due to his “critique of cognitive faculties”- in doing so it simultaneously expresses genuine “speculative” insights as well as downfalls. By asking the question “How are synthetic a priori judgements are possible”, Kant expresses “the authentic Idea of Reason”, because the correct answer to this question, for Hegel, is that the subject and predicate of synthetic judgements are identical. The issue for Hegel is that Kant approached the question in an external manner and as a result remained bound to empty universality. For that reason, one can see “glimpses into the Idea” especially at the point of original synthetic unity of apperception as the principle of synthesis and spontaneity.

The first merit: Apperception and Productive Imagination

To understand Hegel’s point about the apperception, we need to delve into Kant. It is the principle of synthesis of forms of intuition and of all the manifold in our representations. (CPR: A 106, A 117, B 131-9, 150-3, 160-1). What Kant correctly grasps, for Hegel, is that the unity of apperception is an original identity, not a generated product out of the opposites:

Now no cognitions can occur in us, no connection and unity among them, without that unity of consciousness that precedes (my emphasis) all data of the intuitions, and in relation to which all representation of objects is alone possible. This pure, original, unchanging consciousness I will now that of the a name transcendental apperception. That it deserves this name is already obvious from this, that even the purest objective unity, namely priori concepts (space and time) is possible only through the relation of the intuitions to it. The numerical unity of this apperception therefore grounds all concepts a priori, just as the manifoldness of space and time grounds the intuitions of sensibility. ” (CPR: A 107)

Just this transcendental unity of apperception, however, makes out of all possible appearances that can ever come together in one experience a connection of all of these representations in accordance with laws. For this unity of consciousness would be impossible if in the cognition of the manifold the mind could not become conscious of the identity of the function by means of which this manifold is synthetically combined into one cognition. Thus the original and necessary consciousness of the identity of oneself is at the same time a consciousness of an equally necessary unity of the synthesis of all appearances in accordance with concepts, i.e., in accordance with rules that not only make them necessarily reproducible, but also thereby determine an object for their intuition, i.e., the concept of something in which they are necessarily connected; for the mind could not possibly think of the identity of itself in the manifoldness of its representations, and indeed think this a priori, if it did not have before its eyes the identity of its action, which subjects all synthesis of apprehension (which is empirical) to a transcendental unity, and first makes possible their connection in accordance with a priori rules. ” (CPR: A 108)

While the intuition is immersed in the manifold and sensibility gives us forms of intuition, the intellect goes through the appearances and finds laws through them – or, in Kant’s terms, the intellect (understanding) is:

“…itself the legislation for nature, i.e., without understanding there would not be any nature at all, i.e. synthetic unity of the manifold of appearances in accordance with rules, for appearances… exist only in our sensibility.”

The understanding is the higher potency; the manifold in which the intuition is submerged and is undifferentiated only comes to be differentiated through the intellect and as a result comes to be opposed to the intellect itself. In other words, the identity of the intellect (understanding) is not to be submerged within the manifold like the intuition is, where there is no unity because there is no difference, but to “set itself against the manifold” (F&K, 70). In doing this, it sets its identity, in contrast to the intuition, as something opposed against the manifold – it cannot be captured by the manifold. It coarses through it, setting laws which are its own and to which the manifold must obey – thereby constituting itself, the intellect, as an universality. In this sense, it maintains this unity by excluding itself from this manifold. Without this same manifold, however, the concept would empty, which is why it is necessary, and despite its self-exclusion, is identical to it (else there would be no point of contact).

            It is here we must ask ourselves the obvious question – why are they identical? What is the prerequisite which enables the contact in the first place? With this in mind, since apperception is that which underlies the possibility of all and any knowledge and precedes all data of intuition, we have to inquire into what the form of that knowledge is. This is what Hegel especially praised in Kant: the transcendental unity of imagination. This is the pure form of all possible knowledge and through which all objects must be represented a priori. In this way, the genuine speculative dimension for Hegel consists in the fact that the original synthetic unity of apperception presupposes an originary synthesis – meaning, it presupposes a synthesis prior to itself which is absolutely posited; and this is precisely the “productive imagination”, the pure form of the knowledge that the apperception presupposes, since it is itself the condition of knowledge. If the apperception is to be a priori, then this presupposition as well must be considered necessary and a priori. In other words, this is the positing of presuppositions – through deducing the apperception, Kant discovers that this itself contains a presupposition that is necessarily a priori if the former is to be a priori.

            It is important to explain what positing of presuppositions mean. Kant’s deduction of a necessary originary synthesis is something that he arrived through the very process of deducing apperception – meaning, he did not presuppose it from the beginning (in which case it would not count as a speculative insight for Hegel). Kant’s discovery amounts to realizing that this presupposition can only be reached through the process itself –  this presupposition thereby incorporates the process in itself as something that is not external to its content, but immanent, and this necessity is retroactive. This is what it means to be self-determining – the greatest speculative insight in Kant is precisely this transcendental imagination. As Kant himself states:

“The principle of the necessary unity of the pure (productive) synthesis of the imagination prior to apperception is thus the ground of the possibility of all cognition, especially that of experience. “

               So what does the transcendental imagination do? It is the very connection of the manifold a priori. Kant is then capable of recognizing that the unity of apperception in relation to the synthesis of the imagination is the empirical understanding, while the unity of apperception in relation to transcendental synthesis of the imagination is the pure understanding – the cognitions that are a priori conditions of the ordinary understanding, and which themselves contain the synthesis of pure (productive) imagination. These cognitions are the categories of pure understanding, the very same understanding (or intellect) described above.

            We can now go back to Hegel’s thesis about Reason being the identity of the subjective and objective (particular subject and predicate). The productive imagination is a “truly speculative Idea” (F&K: 71) because it is not something that is produced out of the antithesis and needs the manifold of the antithesis to construct itself; it is self-positing and precedes the antithesis. The transcendental synthesis of the productive imagination is the very connection of the manifold in knowledge – it fits Hegel’s notion of being the identity of the heterogenous elements, subjective and objective – intuition and understanding that the apperception unites. But, the following point is equally important for Hegel: as the original identity, it is also that out of which intuition and intellect are respectively sundered from, and as a result made separate from each other as separate faculties. They remain so.

Problem: Judgement

In order to understand the crux of Hegel’s critique, we need to inquire into how does this manifest itself? This is where it is necessary to turn to judgements, or as Kant says “the power of judgements” (CPR: B: 177/A: 138) to show the possibility of, and how, pure concepts of understanding are applied to appearances. As Kant goes on to prove the necessity of a mediating term between the previously mentioned two (transcendental schema: CPR A: 139/B: 178), the next question that concerns us is what is the relation of the pure principles of the understanding and the forms of judgements. Hegel notes that the absolute identity (the imagination) in the judgement is the copula “is, without consciousness” (my emphasis) (F&K: 72). Because the judgement implies separation and difference, the absolute identity is something that is immersed in the absolute antithesis, and not something that truly unites them – since it’s not cognized. Instead of uniting them, because it’s utterly unthought as being merely the copula, it just delineates and sharpens the difference between the subject and predicate (which, if you’ll recall, is opposed to Hegel’s thesis). The latter two are all that is posited within the judgement as that which may be thought (or, as objects of thought) – while the identity of the universal and the particular, the “is”, is the “non-conscious­” element of the judgement.

            What Hegel warns against is thinking that the productive imagination is simply a middle term that is contingently inserted between subject and object (world) – it is the very original identity out of which the subject and the objective world sunder themselves into appearance and product. The problem is that Kant remains at the level of sundering only – he can only cognize Reason as it appears within the empirical (finite) domain. What this means for Hegel is that Kant correctly established the In-itself, which is encapsulated by the power of imagination (as absolute identity). Since he could only see the duplication of this power in terms of the judgement (which is relative identity, opposed to the absolute identity of the imagination) and as that of the universal and the particular (which in Hegel’s eyes is relative duplication) the absolute identity was made relative. The result of this is that, according to Hegel, it became fixated as the intellect (i.e. understanding) and merely universal without content. Because of this, it can only find itself in opposition to the empirical. Hegel is arguing that the judgement in Kant does not necessitate a priori inference – it does not achieve the demonstration of the passage from the appearing of the in-itself to the cognition of the in-itself. There is a lack of correlation between the in-itself (absolute identity) and for-itself (unthought, purely universal rational identity). This is why Hegel sarcastically remarks:

“It is for this reason that the absolute judgment of idealism as expounded by Kant [i.e., the synthetic judgment a priori] may, and, on this level [the Potenz of Reason as intellect], and must be grasped in such a way that the manifold of sensibility, empirical consciousness as intuition and sensation, is in itself something unintegrated, that the world is in itself falling to pieces, and only gets objective coherence and support, substantiality, multiplicity, even actuality and possibility, through the good offices of human selfconsciousness and intellect.”

Problem 2: Thing-in-itself

By limiting Reason, Kant also made the whole world dependent upon Reason itself. This demonstrates Kant’s failure for Hegel – by trying to limit Reason and stop the understanding’s arrogance, as he himself says in Critique of Judgement, he did exactly the opposite. This can also be seen in relation to the things-in-themselves. Things-in-themselves can only be objectively determined if there is “man’s own perspective and projection” (F&K: 74). Because sensation and things-in-themselves are beyond man’s cognition, the sensation that the subject experiences are themselves not a priori (grounded in the subject’s cognition) and for Hegel, it seems that the two (the subject and the world as it is) co-exist only by being radically separated from one another, while the objective still depends upon the subject to have some determinateness. Nonetheless, Kant does have speculative insights here; relations of appearances as judgements in the proofs of necessity between e.g. cause and effect. The problem is that this is still subjective, i.e. only from the side of the cognitive subject.  It is true that the judgement does have some relation to the objective – they are identical – but only in form. The content cannot be identical, else this would break the Kantian limits. This is why for Hegel Kant falls into a contradiction when he makes the thing-in-themselves nothing more than an infinite non-identity, “a formless lump”  that is next to the subject and simultaneously a realm of “beauteous nature and contains determinations with respect to which judgement cannot be subsumptive but only reflecting” which Kant declares in the Critique of Judgement (F&K: 76). This means that the realm of things-in-themselves cannot be cognized but can be reflected upon. Because of this the categories of the human subject prove to be accidental and contingent, since they are compared to an infinite, perfect Beyond (recall Hegel’s critique of Protestantism at the beginning of the section).

            If we go the former route, namely the route that we can only cognize appearances and nothing in itself, then the logical conclusion is that we can also only cognize ourselves as appearances. But Kant cheats here for Hegel, as he does concerning the things-in-themselves, when he asserts that this is not the case, and that the intellect is absolute in man. If the intellect is absolute, then how can we explain its contingency which is inferred by the fact that it cannot comprehend the Beyond? This point is also related to Hegel’s critique of Kant’s view on the relationship between the body and the soul – Hegel notes that Kant correctly, in his view, locates the problem in the cognition of the “assumed heterogenity of… the soul and the objects of outer sense” (F&K: 77). But Kant’s solution, according to Hegel, is that he posits that this difference is only outwardly – inwardly, they might be the same. This is why Hegel sarcastically remarks that Kant was not so consistent to his own standpoint after all because:

“As can be seen, it is for the sake of dear mankind and its cognitive faculty, that Kant so little esteems his thought that maybe the two kinds of things are not so heterogeneous in themselves, but only in appearance. He regards this thought as a chance idea about a maybe and not as a rational thought at all.” (F&K: 78)

           The example above demonstrates Kant’s dogmatism. In Hegel’s eyes, Kant is trying avoid the obvious, logical conclusion of his edifice: dualism. In Kant the identity of opposites is present, but the Idea which unites the two is formal and is only the intellect – which, again, can be only opposed to the empirical content. On the other hand, the in-itself that is expressed here are not of the things-in-themselves, but of finite Reason as such. If the intellect, as Kant wants us to believe, is absolute, by remaining subjective it becomes finite and contingent.  What is Kant unable to cognize, according to Hegel, is that the Idea, the intellect, cannot only in principle be a posteriori, but also necessarily in content. What this means is that it is necessary to extend the apriority Kant correctly expressed in the transcendental imagination to be also a genuine aposteriority (which in Kant isn’t, as we’ve explored in the case of judgement). The apriori must not be opposed to that which is aposteriori.  But because in Kant it is, the unity of Reason, which is related to the intellect and judgement and is itself higher than the intellect, is merely empty or formal. This is exactly the problem of Kant’s Practical Reason for Hegel, which, because the noumenal self is separated from the empirical self, is empty and yet for some reason is capable of “giving itself content” in the form of duties independent of the empirical realm (F&K: 81). Hegel argues that this cannot be done and that Kant’s morality is empty, because it is placed in the Beyond. Herein consists Hegel’s opposition to Kant’s thesis of spontaneity and autonomy – this cannot be true if the infinite (Practical Reason), by abstracting from the finite, is thereby limited by it since the two realms are differently legislated and the separation is final (Practical Reason cannot be applied in the realm of causality, and Theoretical Reason cannot be applied in the realm of freedom – noumenal realm). What Kant does not realize in Hegel’s eyes is the fact that by eliminating the empirical realm from the perspective of Practical Reason, he also eliminates the noumenal realm and Practical Reason along with it – and because the noumenal realm, which is supposed to be infinite, and Practical Reason, which is supposed to be free, are conditioned by this fact, they cannot be truly autonomous. On the other hand, theoretical Reason cannot generate its own content either, but has to be supplied by something external to it (thing-in-itself).

For this reason Hegel disapproves of the differentiation between empirical and noumenal self – it does not achieve, by its own standards, what it set out to do. The erroneous nature of Kant’s critique can be most seen in his refutation of the ontological proof for Hegel. Because Kant’s perspective is finitist and does not grasp the nature of the Idea (recall that Hegel considered that the Idea remains empty in Kant), Hegel wholly rejects his refutation.

“This critique positively asserts the absolute opposition of freedom in the form of concept and necessity in the form of being, and brings about the complete victory of nonphilosophy over the horrible delusion that deranged and blinded previous philosophy…Kant made his triumph even more brilliant and comfortable for himself by taking what used to be called the ontological proof of the existence of God in the worst form it is capable of which is the form given to it by Mendelssohn and others. They turned existence into a property so that the identity of Idea and reality was made to look like the adding of one concept to another. Altogether-especially in his refutations-Kant showed a pervasive ignorance of philosophical systems and a lack of any information about them that went beyond purely historical data” (F&K: 85)

Second Merit: Reflecting Judgement

            Lastly, we must consider the second great speculative insight Hegel detected in Kant – the reflecting judgement from the Critique of Judgement (F&K: 86).

“Does judgment, which in the order of our [specific] cognitive powers is a mediating link between understanding and reason, also have a priori principles of its own? Are these principles constitutive, or are they merely regulative (in which case they would fail to prove that judgment has a domain of its own)? Does judgment give the rule a priori to the feeling of pleasure and displeasure, the mediating link between the cognitive power [in general I and the power of desire (just as the understanding prescribes laws a priori to the cognitive power and reason to the power of desire)? “

“So judgment itself must provide a concept, a concept through which we do not actually cognize anything (my emphasis) but which only serves as a rule for the power of judgment itself-but not as an objective rule, to which it could adapt its judgment, since then we would need another power of judgment in order to decide whether or not the judgment is a case of that rule. This perplexity about a principle (whether subjective or objective) arises mainly in those judgments called aesthetic, which concern the beautiful and the sublime in nature or in art. ” (CoJ: Ak 176-179)

            Kant states that this is necessary because:

“For though these judgments do not by themselves contribute anything whatever to our cognition of things, they still belong to the cognitive power alone and prove a direct relation of this power to the feeling of pleasure or displeasure according to some a priori principle… aesthetic judging is directly referred to the feeling of pleasure and displeasure distinguishes it from a certain kind of) logical judging of nature: when experience manifests in things a lawfulness that understanding’s concept of the sensible is no longer adequate to help us understand or explain, judgment can find within itself a principle that refers the natural thing to the uncognizable supersensible (my emphasis), though judgment must use this principle for cognizing nature only in relation to itself.” (CoJ: 169-170)

            What Hegel commends here is the fact that the reflecting judgement (Hegel’s term) as Kant conceived it is the middle term between the empirical and the noumenal – the theoretical reason and the “intellect as pure abstraction” (practical Reason). It is supposed to solve the problem that Hegel criticized above. However, there is still an issue – this middle term is not the suspension of the antitheses between the absolute and relative identity, or differently put, it is not the elevation above the sphere of synthetic judgement a priori whose problems we’ve explored earlier. The reason for this is because this middle term, the reflecting judgement, is uncognizable. Later on, while Kant does conceive of an imagination that is lawful by itself (has absolute autonomy) and concord between the imagination and the intellect (meaning that the intellect can supply the necessary concepts for the representations of the imagination), this can only occur if the Idea is aesthetic – meaning that the representation by the imagination is still something that can’t be captured by any concept of the understanding. The resolution of the antinomy of taste, likewise for Hegel, is a failure, because Reason is still the “undetermined Idea of the supersensuous in us… without any further possibility of its being made comprehensible” (F&K: 86). This is why:

“An esthetic Idea cannot become cognitive because it is an intuition of the imagination for which no concept can ever be found adequate. An Idea of Reason can never be cognitive because it contains a concept of the supersensuous for which no intuition can ever be found commensurate” (CoJ: 342).

Problem: False Middle term

Hegel’s problem with this standpoint is that while Kant does recognize that the antitheses need to vanish, his insight is negative, because he situates this vanishing within his concept of the supersensuous, which, as we’ve established, is uncognizable, and from a Hegelian perspective, is itself negative and finite. Kant did succeed in conceiving beauty as the Idea that is experienced, but again he did not grasp that because there is an antithesis between the sensuous and the supersensuous, the supersensuous is unknowable, not the other way around. The non-intelligibility does not come from the limitations of the understanding, as Kant himself had thought – but when the understanding reifies the difference between a supposed unattainable Beyond and the sensuous realm (recall what was remarked at the beginning of the section; Hegel thought oppositions are necessary, but that they are not the final word). So even though we’re necessarily driven to the Idea, the systematic unity of the Reason, no reality can be predicated of it. According to Hegel, what Kant was unable to realize is that, ironically, he had Reason in its true totality all along in front of him. First, the issue of separation between the empirical and the noumenal: Hegel notes that the most important fact of this separating is that Kant himself was aware of this separation between these two realms, and not only appearance as a product of this separation. What this means is that Kant was implicitly aware of the totality that bonds both the sensuous and the supersensuous. Then he conceived of an intuition that is capable of transcending this boundary. He was also cognizant of the separation between Reason and in-itself; he has the Idea of Reason where the opposed elements are absolutely identical. He even recognized that, as Hegel states, in and for itself it may be possible that nature may truly follow both legislations of freedom and causality grounded within a transcendental principle that reconciles both legislations, something which was considered impossible in the first Critique (Kant explores this question when inquiring into teleology). What Hegel is saying is that there is no distance between the understanding and the empty, but necessarily generated Idea of Reason – the moment you generate the Idea of infinite Reason, you are already within the domain of infinite Reason. So each time Kant is faced with two viewpoints: finite or truly infinite, in Hegel’s terms, he opts for the former every time – rational knowledge always transcends Reason, and in the case of Nature, the concord between these legislations is a postulate whose guarantee lies in a transcendent deity incomprehensible to man. Let us also here recall the example that Hegel himself doesn’t cite, but encapsulates this point clearly: In the Anthropology, Kant himself had thought that if God entered into the phenomenal world, and revealed himself in all of his splendor, the subject’s freedom in that moment would vanish – from a Hegelian perspective, this position is untenable because it implies an opposition between freedom and necessity. This is why the subjective insight is always made absolute – and yet Kant was also the one who recognized in the intuition of beauty the supersensuous (F&K: 91). This is why Hegel states:

“The truly speculative aspect of Kant’s philosophy can only consist in the Idea being thought and expressed so definitely, and the pursuit of this side of his philosophy is the only interesting aspect of it. This makes it all the harder to see the Rational being muddled up again, and not just that, but to see the highest Idea corrupted with full consciousness, while reflection and finite cognition are exalted above it.” (F&K: 92)

            What Kant is unable to conceive of is the role negativity has, and that the lack of correlation between the in-itself and for-itself are itself moments within the unity of the Idea, not an indication of its failure. For Hegel, Kant could not achieve this insight, because he equated Idea as totality of the empirical+noumenal with the finite intellect – he was unable to see, to put it in Heideggerian terms, the ontological difference between the finite and the true infinite (which is why Hegel rejects Kant’s refutation of the ontological proof of God – the only infinity Kant can conceive of is bad i.e. finite infinity, and the infinity of the Idea, as the unity, cannot be equated to an infinity that is limited by, or abstracts from either of the elements within the unity – and this is what Kant does in the case of the noumenal realm and Practical Reason). Because of this he always has formal identity that is supplied, or supervened by something that is foreign to it (which in reality, within the totality of the Idea, isn’t): the culmination of this movement in Kant is the supersensuous in the Critique of Judgement. What is never explained as a result of this is the bond between practical reason and theoretical reason, the super-sensuous and the sensuous. Because the middle is un-cognizable, the identities within these antitheses are poor and incomplete. As Hegel remarks, Kant’s statement that these antitheses do presuppose a middle (which we’ve explored in the case of productive/transcendental imagination and reflecting judgement) that reconciles the elements i.e. nullifies the antitheses is not true because this very bond is inaccessible to finite Reason, meaning it cannot know the reconciliation. For Hegel, this simply means there is no reconciliation.

“…it is only a confession that there ought to be a Reason. And it is all [the middle] posited in a faith, whose content itself is empty because the antithesis, which as absolute identity could be its own content (my emphasis), has to remain outside it; expressed positively, the content of this faith would be Reasonlessness, because it is an absolutely un-thought, unknown and incomprehensible Beyond (my emphasis).” (F&K: 94)

Conclusion

The inability to allow the absolute identity to be its own content because of the unawareness of the Idea is the hallmark of Kantian philosophy for Hegel. His critique essentially does the opposite of what it claims: by limiting the intellect he also makes the whole world dependent upon it (case of determination of the things-in-themselves), by exalting it as absolute in man he simultaneously shows its contingency in face of the Beyond (reflecting judgement), and in conceiving the autonomy and spontaneity of the Practical Reason, the infinite freedom of the individual, by abstracting from the empirical world he makes that freedom empty and vacuous (erroneous equation of Idea = intellect, which is just one element within the unity of the Idea). Kant is the prime example of the philosophy of reflexive subjectivity from within the domain of Protestantism – he declares that it is enough to know this world, and yet the structure he adopts in order to do so says otherwise. Hegel’s account of Kant essentially consists in that his critique failed to do what it promised it would do. The inequality, contradictory nature of the Kantian system that manifests as a result, encapsulated in the example of imagination-judgement we’ve explored above, is due to the fact he did not grasp what the middle term is. And as we’ve seen in Hegel’s criticism of Protestantism – like the Protestant consciousness, which is aware that the inward must be externalized in order for it to be true, but rejects the external world – the Kantian system does exactly the same. It knows that the inward must be externalized, and yet the external is always something that is foreign to the subject and something that also depends upon the consciousness of man (thing-in-itself) even though the whole system’s supposed point is that it is a critique of man’s cognitive faculties. We’ve also seen how in the last stroke it inverts this thesis by also simultaneously positing that the supersensuous realm, instead of being a non-identity, is made transcendent of human intellect, even though this contradicts Kant’s thesis that the intellect is absolute in man, since it makes this very same intellect contingent. Kant’s critical edifice, in Hegel’s eyes, becomes dogmatic. But we’ve also seen that Hegel recognizes genuinely speculative insights that Kant had made in transcendental imagination and the reflecting judgement.  Even if he did opt for finitude at every stroke, Kant did stick to his postulates – something that Fichte, according to Hegel, although he advocated that he was expounding the true spirit of Kantian philosophy, did not do (which is why, paradoxically, in Hegel’s account he will represent the culmination of reflexive philosophy). Kant’s Reason is pure negativity that is still limited by the positivity of the empirical world. Nonetheless, it is also in discovering this absolute opposition between the concept and the world that:

“…we shall find nothing else expressed in it but the Idea that Reason does have absolute reality, that in this Idea the antithesis of freedom and necessity is completely suspended, that infinite thought is at the same time absolute reality – or in short we shall find the absolute identity of thought and being (my emphasis).” (F&K: 94)